Shubtill v Director of Public Prosecutions: Difference between revisions

no edit summary
No edit summary
No edit summary
Line 93: Line 93:
It would be similarly perverse, Dame Marjorie reasons, if, in the heart of the very same city, a man could not exercise a licence without being arrested. I find force in this submission.
It would be similarly perverse, Dame Marjorie reasons, if, in the heart of the very same city, a man could not exercise a licence without being arrested. I find force in this submission.
====Respondent’s submissions====
====Respondent’s submissions====
Sir Anthony opened brightly for the respondent, arguing that the complainants’ behaviour did not attain the clarity the [[common law]] requires to construe a licence. To the contrary, he says, it hardly could be further from it.
Sir Anthony opened brightly for the respondent. He invoked a principle of his own invention which he calls “[[unequivocality]]”. With it he argues that for the common law to construe a licence based solely upon behaviour, that behaviour must be unequivocal. In their carry-on, the complainants failed to convey the clarity the [[common law]] requires.


We should not expect citizens to conduct their relations with the world in careful syllogisms: Sir Anthony concedes this would be too much. We agree: polite society lubricates its gears with subtle gestures. Nods, winks and waggled heads are quite enough to covey assent. The appellant knows this well.<ref>''[[Shubtill v Port Authority of Finchley]]''</ref>
Now, we should not expect citizens to conduct their relations with the world in careful syllogisms: Sir Anthony concedes this would be too much. We agree: polite society lubricates its gears with subtle gestures. Nods, winks and waggled heads are quite enough to covey assent. The appellant knows this well.<ref>''[[Shubtill v Port Authority of Finchley]]''</ref>


We should not, Sir Anthony urges, lightly impute an open invitation to make mess of on a citizen just because that citizen is aggravating. The common law has long expected citizens to approach it [[Reasonable|reasonably]] and having washed their hands; it does not require them, beyond that, not to be tiresome. The mythical reasonable man is naturally a bore.<ref>''[[Fardell v Potts]]''</ref> The court agrees. We find as fact the complainants ''were'' annoying, and as law that it makes no difference: they are entitled to civil protection.
But nor , Sir Anthony urges, should we lightly impute an open invitation to make mess of a citizen’s oufit, just because that citizen is irksome. The common law has long expected citizens to approach it [[Reasonable|reasonably]] and having [[Clean hands|washed their hands]]; it does not require them, beyond that, not to ''grate''. To the contrary, the [[Reasonable person|reasonable man]] is famously a bore.<ref>''[[Fardell v Potts]]''</ref>


The appellants must, therefore, do enough to raise a basic sense of ''coherence'' to the the complainants’ contact as to at least raise the presumption of a licence.
The court agrees. We find in ''fact'' the complainants ''were'' annoying, and in ''law'' that this makes no difference: they are entitled to civil protection notwithstanding.  


And Ms. Bott’s cloth-headed oration, he contends, was nowhere near coherent. It was little short of baffling: a confused assemblage of illogicalities, sophistries, begged questions, trite slogans, miscued rhetoricals and conclusions not even hinted at by their premises. One could not with safety say that [[Violet Elizabeth Bott|Ms Bott]] understood herself.
Sir Anthony contends that the appellants must, therefore, establish a basic sense of ''coherence'' to the  complainants’ behaviour before there is any talk of a licence.


“What,” asks Sir Anthony, “is one make of someone whose tee-shirt says “Just Stop Oil”, but who carries on to decry the cost of energy? What kind of moron demonstrates about hunger,” he continues, “by tipping away soup? Ms. Bott’s behaviour was a cry for professional help, not for a face-ful of soup.
And Ms. Bott’s cloth-headed oration, he contends, had nothing of the sort. It was baffling: a confused assemblage of illogicalities, sophistries, begged questions, trite slogans, miscued rhetoricals and conclusions not even hinted at by what premises there were. One could not with safety say that [[Violet Elizabeth Bott|Ms. Bott]] understood herself.


We were much persuaded by this line. Sir Anthony closed his submissions rather ingeniously. He invoked a principle of his own invention which he calls “unequivocality”. A [[licence]] such as this, granted by deed rather than compact, requires a clarity of conduct such that a prudent bystander could not misunderstand the complainants’ intent. Sir Anthony invites us to call to mind the “officious bystander” who first assisted the common law as long ago as 1939.<ref>{{cite|Southern Foundries| Shirlaw|1939|2 KB|206}}</ref> Somewhat presumptuously paraphrasing MacKinnon LJ, Sir Anthony suggested:
“What,” asks Sir Anthony, “is one make of someone whose tee-shirt says “Just Stop Oil”, but who carries on to decry the cost of energy? What kind of moron demonstrates about hunger,” he continues, “by tipping away soup? Ms. Bott’s behaviour was a cry for professional help, not for a face full of soup.”
{{Quote|
 
The statement inferred requires conduct so obvious that it goes without saying; so that, if, while the complainants were ensouping the picture and heckling passers by, an officious bystander were to explain what with her conduct the complainant was inviting, they would testily suppress him with a common “Oh, of course!”.}}
We were much persuaded by Sir Anthony’s submissions on this point (even though, apparently, the complainants were not). Had he stopped there, we might have found for the respondent.
 
But, in closing his submissions Sir Anthony gave us pause, not because his arguments are wrong, but because they are ''right''. Sir Anthony invited us to call to mind the “[[officious bystander]]” who first assisted the common law as long ago as 1939.<ref>{{cite|Southern Foundries| Shirlaw|1939|2 KB|206}}</ref> The test for [[unequivocality]] should be, broadly the same: A [[licence]] such as this requires a clarity of conduct such that an officious bystander would understand the complainants’ intent. Somewhat presumptuously paraphrasing MacKinnon LJ in <nowiki>''</nowiki>Southern Foundries v Shirlaw<nowiki>''</nowiki>, Sir Anthony suggested:
{{Quote|The statement inferred requires conduct so obvious that it goes without saying; so that if, while the complainants were ensouping the picture and heckling passers by, an [[officious bystander]] were to explain what the complainant was inviting with her conduct, the respondent would testily suppress him with a common “Oh, of course!”}}


===Judgment===
===Judgment===
This last submission may have been an ingenuity too far. For while the “[[officious bystander]]” was, in MacKinnon LJ’s reckoning, an objective measure, derived by reference to the mythical “amateur referee on Clapham Common” — a hypothetical figure known to all in a modern society, here we need not conjecture how an ''imaginary'' officious bystander would have reacted, because here there was an actual one: the appellant.
This is an excellent way of framing the issue. Sir Anthony may yet regret it, however. For however neat a statement of the law, by way of fact, it does not help his case.
 
The “[[officious bystander]]” was, in MacKinnon LJ’s original reckoning, an ''objective'' measure, derived by reference to that hypothetical figure known to all in a modern society, the “amateur referee on Clapham Common”. Unlike the reasonable man, the officious bystander is not “devoid of human weaknesses, without a single saving vice”<ref>''[[Fardell v Potts]]''</ref>, but is rather shot through with them. He is, after all, officious: pedantic, literal, punctilious, parochial, small-minded, given to wielding the small authorities life bestows upon him for simple pleasure of wreaking inconvenience of others.
 
But here is the thing: when it comes to deciding how such an officious bystander would have reacted, we need not conjecture. We have no need of an ''imaginary'' such figure, because we have an actual one: the appellant himself. he is just the judgmental twerp the court in ''Shirlaw'' had in mind. Here we find a paradox: we fabricate our “objective” test from the lived experiences of common folk ''—'' each by its own terms subjective ''—'' as they are assembled in the imagination, likewise personal, of those who sit in judgment on them. Somehow, the court must extrude from this collection of biases objective truth. We fear at its root they may be just the same.
 
The appellant’s proposition is that, having loudly announced their stance, the complainants are not well positioned to object should someone else follow it. What is soup for a goose is soup for a gander, so to speak. By their own actions, the complainants licensed those who found them irritating to cover them in soup. We have as support for that proposition the fate that then befell them. ''Res ipsa loquitur''.


The appellant’s proposition is that, having loudly announced their stance, the complainants are not well positioned to object should someone else follow it. What is soup for a goose is soup for a gander, so to speak. By their own actions, the complainants licensed those who found them irritating to cover them in soup.
{{Right|''Appeal allowed.''}}


</div>
</div>
{{sa}}
{{sa}}
*[[Albert Haddock]]
*[[Albert Haddock]]