Doubt

In some types of crime — burglary, say — we should expect little direct evidence: competent burglars target unmonitored environments where there are no witnesses. We install alarms and security cameras not to catch burglars, but to dissuade them from trying.

But there could hardly be a worse environment for “getting away with murder” than a neonatal intensive care unit. Entry and exit is monitored and audited. Medications are controlled, secured and their administration regulated. A ward is rarely free of medically qualified witnesses, who conduct rounds and check on patients around the clock. Evading detection would require a skillfully devious expert. You would expect such a malfeasor to refine a careful technique and stick with it.

So it is a curious feature of the “healthcare serial murder” cases that no-one sees the suspect causing actual harm. Even the circumstantial evidence gathered tends not to positively implicate a defendant, but rather put her in a place where she could have commited the crimes, without positively implying she actually did.

Whatever the reason for it, a lack of direct evidence does mean something: there will always always be doubt. No one saw anything. Inference is needed. The question is whether the prosecution has done enough to remove all reasonable doubt.

Onus

And that is a heavy onus. If it is incumbent on a defendant to prove anything — technically it isn’t, but practically it would be a brave defendant who did not — it is simply that there is some plausible doubt. Any will do. Where a seriously ill patient has died in intensive care, even I expectedly, and nothing points directly to the defendant beyond her presence, there is plausible doubt.

{{Once is an happenstance. Twice is coincidence . Three times is enemy action.

—Ian Fleming, Goldfinger}}

This is what the shift data is so important. Okay one death may have been innocent. Two. Even five. But seven?

The shift data reduces the probability of accident. So the thinking goes, at some point the coincidence of one suspect with all these deaths must tell us something.

And here we run across the “Texas sharpshooter” fallacy.

The other deaths and incidents

The sharpshooter relies on the defendant’s presence or absence during other suspicious collapses. We know there were other collapses for which Lucy was not charged. We don’t know why not. The prosecution hints blackly that “further charges may be forthcoming ” but really? Is nine years not enough to make up your mind? How much longer will they need?

On tonewood and prosecutor’s tunnel vision

Triago: Ho, Ho.
Let not thy witty fool, nor his foolish wit
Besmirch the fruited science of th’ academy.
“A little learning is a dangerous thing” —

Nuncle: Yet not half so dangerous as a lot.

Triago: — So sayeth Pope, you know.

Nuncle: But not the one in Rome:

Queen: Good ser knight: art thou drunk upon the Pierian spring:
A hypoxic draft that suffocates the brain,
So deep no shaft of light can bring it round again?

Triago: My conjecture comports a grain of truth
As pure and true and golden—

Nuncle: — but yet no more roundly causative
Than are the month-past flappings of a Latin papillon
Upon a brewing Filipino typhoon.

JC has, elsewhere waxed long and lyrical about the collection of cognitive biases called prosecutor’s tunnel vision. These biases tend to show up where clinching evidence does not: if there were any clinchers, things would be clinched. Therefore those prosecuting — and, for that matter, defending — start to fixate on finer and finer technical details to win isolated arguments. Once one side goes down a rabbit hole, the other is obliged to follow. Insulin assay tests, entry card swipe data, the significance of skin discolourations — all have been cited as smoking guns for prosecution and defence when they are transparently nothing of the sort.

The fact is, there are very few political, social, and especially personal problems that arise because of insufficient information. Nonetheless, as incomprehensible problems mount, as the concept of progress fades, as meaning itself becomes suspect, the Technopolist stands firm in believing that what the world needs is yet more information.[1]

Neil Postman

Information is fractal. The more you look at it, the more you can create: it subdivides infinitely — there is no bottom — and the more raw information you create, the more possible arguments you can have about it. This is the implication of information theory: the more data points there are, the more unique patterns you can make from them.[2] If we take it that a theory is simply “a pattern of consistent data drawn from available information from which we can draw a valid inference” then the more information you have, the more plausible alternative theories of the case you can make.

In other words, you cannot win an argument by simply descending further into the weeds. Those who have drunkenly debated evangelical Christians, resolute atheists, real ale connoisseurs, or tonewood freaks — JC has done all of these — will know this. The thing about descending into the oubliette is that as the points atomise, the arguments grow more heated and the less difference they can possibly make.

This is the “tonewood” debate in a nutshell: sure, in theory the harmonic resonance of nitrocellulose varnish could affect the sound of an electric guitar, but not so as a mere human could possibly hear it in perfect conditions let alone in the moshpit at the Roxy on a sweaty night in 1976.

Whatever did make Steve Jones’ Les Paul sound like a screaming chainsaw, that is, it wasn’t the varnish.

Zeroing in to draw further inferences will not help. The only way to do it is by zooming out.

Oh come on ref

It is a common enough trajectory: we start with an instinct that, a popular, diligent, young, female nurse from a stable background is the last person you would expect to be a serial murderer. We might chide ourselves about our unconscious bias in favour of such individuals and remind ourselves that since this kind of intuition is not scientific, let alone evidence, we must set it aside and consider the circumstantial evidence as it accumulates on its merits, and “without prejudice”.

But hold on: if we regard purely circumstantial evidence as “evidence that changes the prior likelihood” of the event: evidence that changes the reasonable inferences we would otherwise draw from the baseline facts — then in as much as a defendant’s background and socialisation and mental health reflects a basic statistical likelihood our intuitions are useful. They are, indeed, circumstantial evidence.

All else being equal, how likely is it that a person selected at random is a serial murderer? Needless to say, extremely unlikely. Serial murderers are already very rare in the general population. Wikipedia records 70 in Britain since 1255. Let’s conservatively put the total number of inhabitants in the UK since 1255 at 100m: this makes the incidence of any (known) serial murderer at a bit less than one in 2 million.

Now: what sort of person is more likely to commit serial murder? Overwhelmingly, male: 61 out of the seventy. Male, criminal history, a history of violence or deprivation and diagnosable psychiatric condition.


We may not be able to assign precise probabilities to them, but we can legitimately ask, where there is no direct evidence of actual wrongdoing, what is the probability that a young female professional with a healthy social life, a stable and affluent background, a good circle of friends and no history of criminality, deprivation, instability or mental illness and no motivation — no “criminal propensity” at all, in other words — will, without warning, transform herself into a calculating serial murderer. We can see this probability is very, very low.


concerning only probabilities, then there is a “mathematical” way of articulating what seem to be “biases” of our own: 

, but has some basis in probabilities. She is the last person you would expect. The prior probability here is about as low as it could possibly be.

Then

The amateur expert serial murderer

The unit’s lead consultant Dr Stephen Brearey first raised concerns about Letby in October 2015.

No action was taken and she went on to attack five more babies, killing two.

BBC website

On the face of it, the intensive care unit in a neonatal hospital — which must be as tightly controlled, monitored and overwatched as any place in Britain — is the last place you would embark on a regime of surreptitious serial murder. Better, surely to do it like Harold Shipman did, in the privacy of your consulting rooms, or better still, during a house call.

And once the hospital’s lead consultant had his own suspicions about the Nurse, you would think, she would be under even greater surveillance. Wouldn’t she? So does this not make the lack of direct evidence even more remarkable?

Caption text
Category Daniela Poggiali Lucia de Berk Jane Bolding Lucy Letby
“Incriminating” evidence
  • Took selfies laughing with dead body
  • She had the ability to switch between wings of hospital
  • Fiery temper, played pranks on colleagues
  • Found patients irritating
  • Allegations of thefts of jewellery
Example Example
  • Googled parents
  • That post-it note
  • The increased insulin without corresponding C-peptide in 2 victims
  • Had lots of teddy bears
Motive “She must have just loved killing people” Example Example Example
Actual evidence Correlation between shifts and deaths Example Example Correlation between shifts and deaths
Mitigants
  • Large ward many patients
  • High proportion of very old and terminally ill patients
  • Data collection was pretty ropey
Example Example Example
Alleged Method Pottassium Choloride Example Example Several
Resources Richard Gill blog Example Example New Yorker article

We need to talk about lucy letby podcast

More Witches

Peasant 1: We have found a witch may we burn her?
Peasant 2: Burn her!
Bedevere: How do you know she is a witch?
Peasant 1: She looks like one
Bedevere: Bring her forward.
Woman: I am not a witch
Bedevere:But you are dressed as one
Woman: They dressed me up like this
Peasant 1: We didn't!
Woman: And this isn't my nose it's a false one
Bedevere:Well?
Peasant 1: Well, we did do the nose
Bedevere: The nose?
Peasant 2: And the hat but she is a witch
Peasant 1: Burn her!
Bedevere: Did you dress her up like this?
Peasant 1: No.
Peasant 2: Yes.
Peasant 3: Yes.
Peasant 3: A bit. She has got a wart.
Bedevere: What makes you think she is a witch?
Peasant 1: Well, she turned me into a newt.
Bedevere: A newt?
Peasant 1: I got better.
Peasant 2: Burn her anyway!
Peasant 1: Burn her!
Bedevere: Quiet! There are ways of telling whether she is a witch.
Peasant 1: Are there? What are they? Tell us.
Bedevere: Tell me, what do you do with witches?
Peasant 1: Burn them!
Bedevere: What do you burn apart from witches?
Peasant 1: More witches!
Peasant 2: Wood.
Bedevere: So, why do witches burn?
Peasant 1: Because they're made of wood?
Bedevere: Good!
Bedevere: So, how do we tell whether she is made of wood?
Peasant 1: Build a bridge out of her!
Bedevere: Can you not also make bridges of stone?
Peasant 1: Oh, yeah.
Bedevere: Does wood sink in water?
Peasant 1: No. It floats! Throw her into the pond!
Bedevere: What also floats in water?
Peasant 1: Bread.
Peasant 2: Apples.
Peasant 3: Very small rocks.
Peasant 4: Cider.
Peasant 5: Cherries.
Peasant 6: Gravy.
Peasant 7: Mud.
Peasant 8: Churches.
Peasant 9: Lead.
Arthur: A duck!
Bedevere: Exactly. So, logically —
Peasant 1: If she weighs the same as a duck, she's made of wood.
Bedevere: And, therefore?


Peasant 1: A witch!
Peasant 1: A witch!

David Holmes

JHB: what could have been the tell-tale signs that this woman was a danger? Was there anything that could have given us forewarning? Holmes: “Well, it may not give forewarning but generally speaking, [with] a serial killer of this stature really it’s almost obligatory to have psychopathic traits and they will often show themselves in various ways. ... she was very controlled. She was trying to give the image of a very responsible, caring nurse who would be there in a crisis to save babies and so on and so forth. So she is playing the role of someone who would not be suspected other than the correlation between her and the babies’ deaths.”

“It’s a situation where you have not got any really concrete evidence: one piece, like a CCTV camera footage or a witness, etc, all you’ve got is an accumulation of basically very low-level evidence — coincidences, etc — but when you actually accumulate a large number of these [using] something called a Bayesian analysis, it’s actually more statistically sound to have 100 little arrows pointing towards Lucy and none pointing away from her, and I think that’s how justice was actually reached.”

—Criminologist David Holmes on Sky News, 18 August 2023

Well, to a point. Bayesian analysis starts with a “prior probability” — an initial estimate of the likelihood that “Lucy Letby murdered multiple neonatal infants with no motive, no psychiatric history and no prior tendency” — which is extremely low — and adjusts it to a “posterior probability” on the cumulative effect of the “little arrows” to revise the likelihood of it being true. An accumulation of even weak “little arrows” can increase the “posterior” probability of the hypothesis, but if all the arrows are also consistent with another explanation, their contribution to updating a Bayesian analysis may be modest. There is significant potential for false positives when dealing with rare events and weak evidence. (Compare this with David Bain’s case, where the prior probability that he was the culprit was already high (the event was certainly murder, and he was one of only two plausible suspects), and the circumstantial evidence against him was strong, and Lindy Chamberlain, where the prior probability was very low, and the circumstantial evidence weak).

Prior and posterior probabilities in different cases
Case There was a Murder Suspect responsible Another person responsible
Prior Posterior Prior Posterior Prior Posterior
OJ Simpson Certain Unchanged Very likely Greatly increased Fairly unlikely Unchanged
David Bain Certain Unchanged Fairly likely Greatly increased Fairly likely Greatly decreased
Peter Ellis Very unlikely Mildly increased Extremely unlikely Mildly increased Extremely unlikely Unchanged
Lindy Chamberlain Very unlikely Mildly increased Extremely unlikely Mildly increased Extremely unlikely Unchanged
Lucy Letby Very unlikely Mildly increased Extremely unlikely Mildly increased Extremely unlikely Unchanged

The question, then, is how many of the “little arrows” are inconsistent with another explanation. Here there are two categories of alternative explanation: that someone else was responsible, or that no-one was criminally responsible: the event would have happened anyway.

The prior probability of there being a different murderer on the ward is the same for any other nurse as for Lucy Letby: extremely unlikely. No suggestion was made that any other person was involved, so we can assume two alternatives: either an innocent explanation or Letby was the culprit.

It is worth also looking at the categories of circumstantial evidence in each case and associating it with one or other of those probabilities. Does it make it more likely that There was criminality involved in the deaths, or that, Assuming there was criminality, Letby was the culprit.

Relevance of evidence to probabilities
Evidence Criminality Letby was the culprit
Relevance Posterior value Relevance Posterior value
Ward roster No N/A Yes Contested
Post-it Note No N/A Yes Weak
Editing nursing notes to “cover tracks” Yes Weak Yes Contested
Post-event internet activity No N/A Yes Weak
“Trophy” handover notes No N/A Yes Weak
Bubbly personality No N/A No N/A
Obsession with a married doctor No N/A No N/A
Unexpected collapse Yes Weak No N/A
Insulin levels Yes Weak No N/A
Skin discolouration Yes Weak No N/A
Liver damage Yes Weak No N/A
Evidence of air in blood and brain Yes Weak No N/A

Interestingly, bar for the alleged editing of nursing notes, which case been oddly under-reported, none of the “small arrows” point to both the presence of criminality and Letby’s particular involvement. It is worth reviewing the published pieces of the chief “public prosecutors” who make the case for Letby’s guilt. Among these are the expert witness Dr Dewi Morris, Daily Mail Journalist Liz Hull,[3] BBC Journalist Judith Moritz and the frequently interviewed Criminologist David Holmes. They are emphatic in their dismissal of the “yellow butterfly gang” — in Hull’s words, “diverse band of fanatics and pseudo-scientists” (later upgraded to a “strange band of misfits and ghouls”) coming from all “walks of society: well-to-do pensioners, middle-aged women, and the unemployed” and who, er, “counted scientists, neo-natal nurses, doctors and statisticians among their members” — so I was curious to see what they brought out as their clinchers.

Lizz Hull

Hull, on the New Yorker piece:

I’ve read the article and now the retrial is over I can write about it. And while there’s no doubting the author, who says she obtained full transcripts of the ten-month trial at huge cost, has researched the case thoroughly, it contains errors and cherry-picks evidence, omitting large parts of the prosecution case which was pivotal in reaching a conviction.

For example, it makes no mention of the 250 confidential “trophy” handover notes, blood test results and resuscitation notes relating to the babies police found at Letby’s home; it does not try to explain the Facebook searches that she made for the parents of her victims, years after she harmed their children.

Letby’s abnormal, animated behaviour in front of grieving parents after a baby died and pictures of cards she sent or received from parents of babies she murdered that were stored on her mobile phone, are also ignored, as is her obsession with a married doctor and her deliberate editing of nursing notes to make it seem like a baby was on the verge of collapse to cover her tracks.[4]

In a later article on 24 July 2024 — the first one evidently not having the desired effect — Hull sets out the overlooked evidence that proves the conspiracy theorists (although they are better described as “no conspiracy theorists”) wrong.

Star witness Dr Dewi Evans

Uncalled defence expert Mike Hall

Sewage and insulin

  • No evidence was presented to show any of the infants contracted bacterial or parasitic infections linked to dirty water caused by drainage problems.
  • Though journalists have since queried the suitability of the insulin tests for use in a criminal prosecution, the defence team did not.

Concession that the insulin was deliberate

The Court reporting suggests this was less emphatic than it has been made out to be:[5]

Letby is asked if Child E was poisoned with insulin.
“Yes I agree that he had insulin.”
“Do you believe that somebody gave it to him unlawfully?”
“Yes.”
“Do you believe that someone targeted him?”
“No.”
“It was a random act?”
“Yes...I don't know where the insulin came from.”
“Do you agree [Child L] was poisoned with insulin?”
“From the blood results, yes.”
“Do you agree that someone targeted him specifically?”
“No...I don't know how the insulin got there.”
Letby adds: “I don’t believe that any member of staff on the unit would make a mistake in giving insulin.”

Liver injury

One of the babies suffered significant liver trauma. The post-mortem said the bleed was due to vigorous CPR, but a forensic pathologist from told the jury he’d only ever seen this type of extensive internal injury in children involved in road, trampolines cycling accidents, or who had been deliberately assaulted.

Letby accepted in evidence that the injury took place “on her watch”.

Air in stomachs

The Guardian reported that seven anonymous neonatologists called Dr Evans’ theory about the injection of air into the stomach via nasal feeding tubes “ridiculous”.

Dr Evans admitted to me that injecting air in a nasogastric tube is “utterly bizarre” and something he’d never heard of before. But he added: “That doesn't mean it can’t exist.”

The shift rota

The infamous shift rota chart was not created after the fact, so the “Texas sharpshooter” argument falls over. Dr Evans reviewed all cases bar one were looked at “blind” months, before Letby’s name was disclosed to him.

Dr Evans says Cheshire police did not put together the shift graph until he had identified suspected cases. Only when officers cross-checked those events with staff on duty did the striking pattern of Letby’s presence emerge.

The rash

The argument that prosecution expert witnesses misdiagnosed a rash based on misreading Dr Shoo Lee’s 1989 report on the air embolism phenomenon. Dr Lee told Letby’s appeal he believed the rashes were not diagnostic of the condition.

But Dr Lee did not have access to the medical notes or witness statements when making this assessment and his evidence was ruled inadmissible.

The screaming

Hull describes “harrowing testimony of parents, doctors and nurses” of uncharacteristic “screaming” from several of the premature babies, who likely suffered extreme pain.

Letby, the Prosecution said, had rammed a medical instrument down the boy's throat moments earlier, causing internal bleeding. She later injected him with air to kill him.

Letby’s behaviour

On one occasion Letby told a colleague a baby “looked pale” when no lights were on in the nursery, and her face was obscured by a canopy. That child had stopped breathing but was resuscitated only to die by alleged air injection the next day.

The cards, googling and condolences.

Bayesian probabilities applied to other questions

As Tom Chivers notes in his excellent Everything Is Predictable: How Bayes’ Remarkable Theorem Explains the World, a fellow newly armed with Bayesian techniques is the proverbial “man with a hammer”: once you learn how to do it, it is hard to resist applying it to all kinds of questions not usually seen as the domain of statistics.

For example: miscarriages of justice are, as far as we know, extremely rare: those in the population of murder convicts across history — which surely numbers in the millions — who were justly convicted enormously outweigh those who were unjustly convicted, which we can put in the hundreds or thousands (Wikipedia lists just fifty-four). This might lead to the conclusion that a person who has been convicted by a jury is, ipso facto, highly unlikely to be innocent: that is, after all, the fundamental design goal of the justice system.

But the number convicted of “medical carer serial murders” in history is also small. According to Wikipedia, of nearly 800 serial killers fewer than 60 were medical carers, of whom two-thirds admitted their crimes. Serial murder is rare. Medical carer serial murder is even rarer.

But amongst Healthcare serial murder cases, miscarriages of justice are comparatively common. There are at least five recent examples, all strikingly similar:

  • Lucia de Berk: A Dutch nurse wrongly convicted of multiple murders due to statistical errors and misinterpretation of medical evidence. Her conviction was later overturned.
  • Susan Nelles: A Canadian nurse accused of murdering infants; charges were dropped due to lack of evidence.
  • Ben Geen: A British nurse whose conviction for murdering patients by inducing respiratory arrests was quashed on appeal due to unreliable evidence.
  • Colin Norris: A British nurse convicted of murdering patients by insulin injection; his conviction was later overturned due to flawed medical evidence.
  • Daniela Poggiali: An Italian nurse accused of murdering patients in a hospital. She was initially convicted but later acquitted on appeal due to a lack of conclusive evidence.
  • Jane Bolding: A British nurse accused of murdering patients in her care. She was acquitted after a retrial due to lack of evidence.

The relatively high proportion of miscarriages of justice among “hospital carer” cases raises the “posterior probability” that a given conviction of this type might be wrongful by comparison with other types of murder case where such errors are historically less common.

The multiple modus operandi

An unusual feature, compared with even other hospital carer serial killer cases is the variety of ways by which Letby is alleged to have murdered, or attempted to murder, the children.

  • Insulin in intravenous bags
  • Injection of air into bloodstream
  • Injection of air into stomach via gastric tube
  • Dislodging feeding tube
  • Liver trauma
  • Overfeeding by milk

Two points of significance here: first, serial killers generally develop and stick with a single modus operandi, refining a technique that “works” and avoids leaving evidence or allowing for detection. Leaving no evidence is hard. Second, the more different routes one uses, the more scope there is for evidence or detection.

  1. Neil Postman, Technopoly: The Surrender of Culture to Technology, 1992.
  2. Simply put, if you have one data point, you can make one possible combination. If you have two, you can make three (A, B, AB). If you have three, you can make seven (A,B, C, AB, BC, AC, ABC), and so on.
  3. It is time for this Lucy Letby is innocent madness to stop, Liz Hull, Daily Mail, 19 July 2024
  4. Lucy Letby Conspiracy Theorists are Wrong, Lizz Hull, Daily Mail, 5 July 2024.
  5. Chester Standard report of May 18 2023 (see 12.11pm).
Return to "Lucy Letby" page.