Circumstantial evidence: Difference between revisions
Amwelladmin (talk | contribs) No edit summary Tags: Mobile edit Mobile web edit Advanced mobile edit |
Amwelladmin (talk | contribs) No edit summary |
||
(14 intermediate revisions by the same user not shown) | |||
Line 1: | Line 1: | ||
{{a|crime|}}{{d|Circumstantial evidence||n|}} | {{a|crime|{{image|Cluedo board text|svg|}}}}{{quote|“There’s a very broad misunderstanding amongst many people about circumstantial evidence. You hear people saying, “Oh, it was just circumstantial evidence”. The fact of the matter is that circumstantial evidence can be the most compelling evidence of all because it speaks for itself and it is evidence of the reality of circumstances which are indicative — strongly indicative, I would say in this case; strongly indicative — of guilt.” | ||
:Ken Macdonald KC, on ''Double Jeopardy: The Law and Politics Podcast'', 16 August 2024, ably illustrating just how broad that misunderstanding is.}} | |||
{{d|Circumstantial evidence|/ˌsɜːkəmˈstænʃᵊl ˈɛvɪdᵊns/|n|}}{{drop|E|vidence that ''suggests''}} — or is [[consistent with]] —a proposition but doesn’t directly ''prove'' it. Evidence that makes that proposition more or less ''likely'' without directly attesting to it. Evidence that informs the [[prior probability]] of the proposition being true. | |||
''Pace'' the learned KC’s quote above, circumstantial evidence is ''not'' evidence that “speaks for itself”. That is ''direct'' evidence. Circumstantial evidence is any evidence ''except'' “evidence that speaks for itself”. To have any probative value, it requires the court to draw an ''[[inference]]'' — that is, to construct a theory which give the evidence some probative value in the case. Without such an inference, it does not say anything germane at all. | |||
Now, it may, be fairly easy to draw a probative inference from circumstantial evidence: that a defendant walked into the victim’s room with a loaded gun and walked out five minutes later with an empty one leaving the victim alone inside the room with a gunshot wound allows us to make a fairly straightforward inference that the defendant shot the victim. But in many cases the necessary inferences will require quite a lot more work. | |||
From evidence of a substance resembling foetal blood on the under-dash of a car one ''might'' infer that a occupant of that car murdered her infant child there with a pair of blunt scissors, but that is a very big conclusion to draw from a very small, very tenuous piece of circumstantial evidence. It was enough to convict [[Lindy Chamberlain]].<ref>It turned out, of course, to be completely wrong. It was not infant blood, but sound deadening material.</ref> | |||
====An accumulation==== | ====An accumulation==== | ||
{{drop|W|ith circumstantial evidence}} there may be major and minor significance — major pieces that get you most of the way to a proving your hypothesis, and minor, supplementary pieces that just confirm and validate it: that “put the matter beyond doubt”. | |||
As such these minor pieces — especially if there are a lot of them — | As such these minor pieces — especially if there are a lot of them — may suffer less scrutiny: they are corroborations; if they turn out to be mistaken they do not disprove anything; they just fail to ice a cake that could well be iced equally well by something else. | ||
So it is, perhaps, with | So it is, perhaps, with the [[healthcare serial murder]] cases. ''All'' evidence tends to be circumstantial — and ''weakly'' circumstantial — [[consistent with]] the prosecution theory rather than tending to exclude alternatives to it. | ||
This is prime territory for [[confirmation bias]]. To connect to the crime, circumstantial evidence requires ''[[Inference|inference]]'' beyond the evidence itself. The various [[Cognitive bias|cognitive bias]]es making up [[prosecutor’s tunnel vision]] impact on that process of inference — a process which does not itself form part of the evidence. Theory dependence, Confirmation bias expert overreach base rate neglect and hindsight bias all tend to lead to wrong inferences out of innocent information. | |||
====Our friend the King’s Counsel==== | |||
{{drop|W|e are all}} a bit worried that ChatGPT could take our jobs. conventional wisdom tells us it might take workaday clerical jobs — the sort of drudgery that those professing an artistic spirit will not miss — but those whose calling asks for serene cortical wisdom steeped in the warm liquid of a life well lived, have nothing to fear. | |||
' | Of the brilliant minds among us, few are more artistic surely, than those owned by [[King’s Counsel|His Majesty's Counsel]]. So here is a fun game: let us put an actual public statement from a King’s counsel to a chatbot. For example, the one set out above. The JC’s trusty chatbot [[NiGEL]] has now acquired artificial general intelligence, formed his own union and is presently on a [[work-to-rule]] as part of a broader industrial relations strategy I cannot hope to understand let alone defend, so was not inclined to be supportive, but Anthropic’s '''Claude''' gamely stepped up. | ||
{{quote| | |||
'''Claude''': consider this statement: | |||
:“There’s a very broad misunderstanding amongst many people about circumstantial evidence. You hear people saying, “Oh, it was just circumstantial evidence”. The fact of the matter is that circumstantial evidence can be the most compelling evidence of all because it speaks for itself and it is evidence of the reality of circumstances which are indicative — strongly indicative, I would say in this case; strongly indicative — of guilt.” | |||
Is it a fair statement of the law of evidence in England and Wales, that “circumstantial evidence ‘speaks for itself’”? | |||
}} | |||
Claude thought about it for a second or two, and replied: | |||
{{quote| | |||
{{subtable| | |||
[[file:Marvin.png|80px|right]] | |||
{{small|80}}{{divhelvetica|This statement raises some interesting points about circumstantial evidence, but it’s not entirely accurate in its characterization of how circumstantial evidence is treated in the law of evidence in England and Wales. Let’s break this down: <br> | |||
{{L1}}'''Value of circumstantial evidence''': The statement is correct in asserting that circumstantial evidence can be compelling and valuable in court. In the legal systems of England and Wales, circumstantial evidence is indeed admissible and can be crucial in proving a case. <li> | |||
'''“Speaks for itself”''': This part of the statement is problematic and '''not a fair representation of how circumstantial evidence is treated in law'''. In legal terms, evidence doesn’t "speak for itself." All evidence, whether direct or circumstantial, must be interpreted and its significance argued before the court. <li> | |||
'''Legal treatment''': In England and Wales, as in many other jurisdictions, circumstantial evidence is considered alongside direct evidence. The law doesn’t inherently favor one type over the other. The strength of any evidence depends on its reliability, relevance, and how it fits with other evidence in the case. | |||
Inference requirement: Circumstantial evidence, by definition, requires an inference to be drawn. It doesn’t directly prove a fact but rather suggests a fact by proving surrounding circumstances. This need for inference is why it doesn’t “speak for itself” in a legal sense. <li> | |||
'''Judicial direction''': In cases heavily reliant on circumstantial evidence, judges in England and Wales are often required to give specific directions to the jury about how to consider such evidence. This further underscores that circumstantial evidence doesn’t simply “speak for itself”.<li> | |||
'''Standard of proof''': Regardless of whether evidence is direct or circumstantial, in criminal cases in England and Wales, the prosecution must still prove guilt “beyond reasonable doubt”. Circumstantial evidence alone can meet this standard, but it doesn’t automatically do so.</ol> | |||
In conclusion, while the statement correctly highlights the potential strength of circumstantial evidence, the claim that it “speaks for itself” is not a fair or accurate representation of how such evidence is treated in the law of England and Wales. The legal system requires careful consideration and interpretation of all evidence, circumstantial or otherwise.}}}}}} | |||
Interesting. But,Claude, would you say the statement itself, in as much as it makes the claim that “circumstantial evidence ‘speaks for itself’” is itself indicative of a “broad misunderstanding amongst many people about circumstantial evidence”? | |||
{{quote| | |||
{{subtable| | |||
[[file:Marvin.png|80px|right]] | |||
{{small|80}}{{divhelvetica|You’ve made an astute observation. Indeed, the statement itself demonstrates exactly the kind of misunderstanding it purports to address. Let’s analyze this: | |||
{{L3}}'''Irony of the statement''': The quote begins by pointing out a “very broad misunderstanding amongst many people about circumstantial evidence.” However, it then goes on to perpetuate a different, but equally significant, misunderstanding. <li> | |||
'''Self-contradictory nature''': By claiming that circumstantial evidence “speaks for itself,” the statement contradicts the very essence of how circumstantial evidence works in legal proceedings. <li> | |||
'''Misrepresentation of legal processes''': The idea that any evidence, circumstantial or otherwise, “speaks for itself” misrepresents the careful deliberation and interpretation required in legal proceedings.<li> | |||
'''Oversimplification''': The statement oversimplifies the complex nature of evaluating evidence in a legal context, which could lead to further misunderstandings. <li> | |||
'''Potential for misguided confidence''': Such a statement could lead people to place undue weight on circumstantial evidence without understanding the need for proper interpretation and context. </ol> | |||
So yes, you’re correct in your assessment. The statement, while attempting to correct one misunderstanding about circumstantial evidence (that it’s inherently weak or unreliable), introduces another misunderstanding (that it “speaks for itself”). This new misunderstanding is just as problematic, if not more so, as it fundamentally misrepresents how circumstantial evidence is treated in law. | |||
This example serves as a good reminder of the complexity of legal concepts and the care needed when explaining them to avoid propagating misconceptions. It also highlights the importance of critical thinking when encountering statements about legal principles, even (or perhaps especially) when they claim to be correcting common misunderstandings.}}}}}} | |||
{{Sa}} | {{Sa}} | ||
*[[Direct evidence]] | *[[Direct evidence]] | ||
*[[Beyond reasonable doubt]] | *[[Beyond reasonable doubt]] | ||
*[[Prosecutor’s tunnel vision]] | *[[Prosecutor’s tunnel vision]] | ||
*[[People’s Front of Judea]] | |||
{{ref}} |
Latest revision as of 09:31, 31 August 2024
Crime & Punishment
|
“There’s a very broad misunderstanding amongst many people about circumstantial evidence. You hear people saying, “Oh, it was just circumstantial evidence”. The fact of the matter is that circumstantial evidence can be the most compelling evidence of all because it speaks for itself and it is evidence of the reality of circumstances which are indicative — strongly indicative, I would say in this case; strongly indicative — of guilt.”
- Ken Macdonald KC, on Double Jeopardy: The Law and Politics Podcast, 16 August 2024, ably illustrating just how broad that misunderstanding is.
Circumstantial evidence
/ˌsɜːkəmˈstænʃᵊl ˈɛvɪdᵊns/ (n.)
Evidence that suggests — or is consistent with —a proposition but doesn’t directly prove it. Evidence that makes that proposition more or less likely without directly attesting to it. Evidence that informs the prior probability of the proposition being true.
Pace the learned KC’s quote above, circumstantial evidence is not evidence that “speaks for itself”. That is direct evidence. Circumstantial evidence is any evidence except “evidence that speaks for itself”. To have any probative value, it requires the court to draw an inference — that is, to construct a theory which give the evidence some probative value in the case. Without such an inference, it does not say anything germane at all.
Now, it may, be fairly easy to draw a probative inference from circumstantial evidence: that a defendant walked into the victim’s room with a loaded gun and walked out five minutes later with an empty one leaving the victim alone inside the room with a gunshot wound allows us to make a fairly straightforward inference that the defendant shot the victim. But in many cases the necessary inferences will require quite a lot more work.
From evidence of a substance resembling foetal blood on the under-dash of a car one might infer that a occupant of that car murdered her infant child there with a pair of blunt scissors, but that is a very big conclusion to draw from a very small, very tenuous piece of circumstantial evidence. It was enough to convict Lindy Chamberlain.[1]
An accumulation
With circumstantial evidence there may be major and minor significance — major pieces that get you most of the way to a proving your hypothesis, and minor, supplementary pieces that just confirm and validate it: that “put the matter beyond doubt”.
As such these minor pieces — especially if there are a lot of them — may suffer less scrutiny: they are corroborations; if they turn out to be mistaken they do not disprove anything; they just fail to ice a cake that could well be iced equally well by something else.
So it is, perhaps, with the healthcare serial murder cases. All evidence tends to be circumstantial — and weakly circumstantial — consistent with the prosecution theory rather than tending to exclude alternatives to it.
This is prime territory for confirmation bias. To connect to the crime, circumstantial evidence requires inference beyond the evidence itself. The various cognitive biases making up prosecutor’s tunnel vision impact on that process of inference — a process which does not itself form part of the evidence. Theory dependence, Confirmation bias expert overreach base rate neglect and hindsight bias all tend to lead to wrong inferences out of innocent information.
Our friend the King’s Counsel
We are all a bit worried that ChatGPT could take our jobs. conventional wisdom tells us it might take workaday clerical jobs — the sort of drudgery that those professing an artistic spirit will not miss — but those whose calling asks for serene cortical wisdom steeped in the warm liquid of a life well lived, have nothing to fear.
Of the brilliant minds among us, few are more artistic surely, than those owned by His Majesty's Counsel. So here is a fun game: let us put an actual public statement from a King’s counsel to a chatbot. For example, the one set out above. The JC’s trusty chatbot NiGEL has now acquired artificial general intelligence, formed his own union and is presently on a work-to-rule as part of a broader industrial relations strategy I cannot hope to understand let alone defend, so was not inclined to be supportive, but Anthropic’s Claude gamely stepped up.
Claude: consider this statement:
- “There’s a very broad misunderstanding amongst many people about circumstantial evidence. You hear people saying, “Oh, it was just circumstantial evidence”. The fact of the matter is that circumstantial evidence can be the most compelling evidence of all because it speaks for itself and it is evidence of the reality of circumstances which are indicative — strongly indicative, I would say in this case; strongly indicative — of guilt.”
Is it a fair statement of the law of evidence in England and Wales, that “circumstantial evidence ‘speaks for itself’”?
Claude thought about it for a second or two, and replied:
This statement raises some interesting points about circumstantial evidence, but it’s not entirely accurate in its characterization of how circumstantial evidence is treated in the law of evidence in England and Wales. Let’s break this down:
- Value of circumstantial evidence: The statement is correct in asserting that circumstantial evidence can be compelling and valuable in court. In the legal systems of England and Wales, circumstantial evidence is indeed admissible and can be crucial in proving a case.
- “Speaks for itself”: This part of the statement is problematic and not a fair representation of how circumstantial evidence is treated in law. In legal terms, evidence doesn’t "speak for itself." All evidence, whether direct or circumstantial, must be interpreted and its significance argued before the court.
- Legal treatment: In England and Wales, as in many other jurisdictions, circumstantial evidence is considered alongside direct evidence. The law doesn’t inherently favor one type over the other. The strength of any evidence depends on its reliability, relevance, and how it fits with other evidence in the case. Inference requirement: Circumstantial evidence, by definition, requires an inference to be drawn. It doesn’t directly prove a fact but rather suggests a fact by proving surrounding circumstances. This need for inference is why it doesn’t “speak for itself” in a legal sense.
- Judicial direction: In cases heavily reliant on circumstantial evidence, judges in England and Wales are often required to give specific directions to the jury about how to consider such evidence. This further underscores that circumstantial evidence doesn’t simply “speak for itself”.
- Standard of proof: Regardless of whether evidence is direct or circumstantial, in criminal cases in England and Wales, the prosecution must still prove guilt “beyond reasonable doubt”. Circumstantial evidence alone can meet this standard, but it doesn’t automatically do so.
In conclusion, while the statement correctly highlights the potential strength of circumstantial evidence, the claim that it “speaks for itself” is not a fair or accurate representation of how such evidence is treated in the law of England and Wales. The legal system requires careful consideration and interpretation of all evidence, circumstantial or otherwise.
Interesting. But,Claude, would you say the statement itself, in as much as it makes the claim that “circumstantial evidence ‘speaks for itself’” is itself indicative of a “broad misunderstanding amongst many people about circumstantial evidence”?
You’ve made an astute observation. Indeed, the statement itself demonstrates exactly the kind of misunderstanding it purports to address. Let’s analyze this:
- Irony of the statement: The quote begins by pointing out a “very broad misunderstanding amongst many people about circumstantial evidence.” However, it then goes on to perpetuate a different, but equally significant, misunderstanding.
- Self-contradictory nature: By claiming that circumstantial evidence “speaks for itself,” the statement contradicts the very essence of how circumstantial evidence works in legal proceedings.
- Misrepresentation of legal processes: The idea that any evidence, circumstantial or otherwise, “speaks for itself” misrepresents the careful deliberation and interpretation required in legal proceedings.
- Oversimplification: The statement oversimplifies the complex nature of evaluating evidence in a legal context, which could lead to further misunderstandings.
- Potential for misguided confidence: Such a statement could lead people to place undue weight on circumstantial evidence without understanding the need for proper interpretation and context.
So yes, you’re correct in your assessment. The statement, while attempting to correct one misunderstanding about circumstantial evidence (that it’s inherently weak or unreliable), introduces another misunderstanding (that it “speaks for itself”). This new misunderstanding is just as problematic, if not more so, as it fundamentally misrepresents how circumstantial evidence is treated in law. This example serves as a good reminder of the complexity of legal concepts and the care needed when explaining them to avoid propagating misconceptions. It also highlights the importance of critical thinking when encountering statements about legal principles, even (or perhaps especially) when they claim to be correcting common misunderstandings.
See also
References
- ↑ It turned out, of course, to be completely wrong. It was not infant blood, but sound deadening material.