Circumstantial evidence: Difference between revisions

From The Jolly Contrarian
Jump to navigation Jump to search
No edit summary
No edit summary
Line 9: Line 9:


From evidence of a substance resembling foetal blood on the under-dash of a car one ''might'' infer that a occupant of that car murdered her infant child there with a pair of blunt scissors, but that is a very big conclusion to draw from a very small, very tenuous piece of circumstantial evidence. It was enough to convict [[Lindy Chamberlain]].<ref>It turned out, of course, to be completely wrong. It was not infant blood, but sound deadening material.</ref>  
From evidence of a substance resembling foetal blood on the under-dash of a car one ''might'' infer that a occupant of that car murdered her infant child there with a pair of blunt scissors, but that is a very big conclusion to draw from a very small, very tenuous piece of circumstantial evidence. It was enough to convict [[Lindy Chamberlain]].<ref>It turned out, of course, to be completely wrong. It was not infant blood, but sound deadening material.</ref>  
====“Direct” versus “circumstantial”====
{{drop|C|ompare circumstantial evidence with}} direct evidence that addresses the allegation without the need for further ''inference''.<ref>In this discussion we will “control” for witness credibility by assuming all witnesses are speaking the unimpeachable truth.</ref>
Take the hypothetical allegation:
{{Quote|Colonel Mustard murdered Reverend Green with a lead pipe in the library.}}
A till receipt in Colonel Mustard’s wallet for a recently purchased length of lead pipe is circumstantial evidence to support this allegation. It is consistent with it, but does not settle it. A further inference is needed — that Colonel Mustard used his lead pipe to murder Reverend Green for which — ''yet'' — we have no evidence. Even if the evidence is fully reliable, the inference may yet be false. the best we can say is that, all else being equal, the till receipt is ''[[consistent with]]'' the allegation. It may increase the probability of the allegation being true — but by itself, not by much.
Not enough to secure a conviction [[beyond reasonable doubt]], but enough to make Colonel Mustard a ''suspect''. As we will see, once you are a suspect, things can change quickly.
But then Mrs. Peacock tells Inspector Clouseau, “I saw Colonel Mustard strike Reverend Green with a lead pipe in the library. He fell down, stone dead”.  This is ''direct'' evidence. If we believe Mrs. Peacock, this evidence will settle the matter. It directly attests to cause and effect. The Colonel’s till receipt corroborates it, but is hardly needed to make out the case. He is already a goner.
You might say that direct evidence establishes ''[[causation]]'' while circumstantial evidence establishes ''[[correlation]]''. One attests that the event ''did'' happen, the other that ''it is more likely'' to have happened.


====An accumulation====
====An accumulation====
With circumstantial evidence there may be major and minor significance — major pieces that get you most of the way to a proving your hypothesis, and minor, supplementary pieces that just confirm and validate it: that “put the matter beyond doubt”.
{{drop|W|ith circumstantial evidence}} there may be major and minor significance — major pieces that get you most of the way to a proving your hypothesis, and minor, supplementary pieces that just confirm and validate it: that “put the matter beyond doubt”.


As such these minor pieces — especially if there are a lot of them — may suffer less scrutiny: they are corroborations; if they turn out to be mistaken they do not disprove anything; they just fail to ice a cake that could well be iced equally well by something else.
As such these minor pieces — especially if there are a lot of them — may suffer less scrutiny: they are corroborations; if they turn out to be mistaken they do not disprove anything; they just fail to ice a cake that could well be iced equally well by something else.


So it is, perhaps, with [[Lucy Letby]]. ''All'' evidence against her was circumstantial. Not just circumstantial but ''weakly'' circumstantial — [[consistent with]] the prosecution theory rather than tending to exclude of alternatives. This is prime territory for [[confirmation bias]]. The “killer fact” — the one piece of accumulated evidence that seems to support the prosecution theory ''to the exclusion of all others'' is the notorious nursing rota, on which she was on duty for every suspicious incident.
So it is, perhaps, with the [[healthcare serial murder]] cases. ''All'' evidence tends to be circumstantial — and ''weakly'' circumstantial — [[consistent with]] the prosecution theory rather than tending to exclude alternatives to it.  
 
Are the remaining evidence weaker? Well, imagine the prosecution case ''without'' that linking evidence. Say we dispel the idea there was a single perpetrator. No nurse had an unusual confluence if shifts.All of the rest of the evidence — blotched skin, dislodged tubes, air in vessels and so on , was still present, and is presented not to a serial murder trial, but to a series of individual trials against different nurses. Now how seriously would we inspect the chain of custody of samples? The suitability of the insulin test? The value of the “[[Consistent with|consistency]]” of the blotching with air embolus? Without this evidence now there is ''no'' case to answer. The fact that Nurse Letby was on duty is of no moment because, well, ''someone'' had to be on duty, and it being Nurse Letby rather than Nurse Smith or Jones tells us nothing about the incident in question.
 
The blotching becomes simply “odd blotching” that could mean anything. The insulin poisoning becomes “an unusual insulin reading”. Analysis of insulin tests are vulnerable to [[base rate neglect]] after all. Especially tests that are not in the first place suitable for forensic purposes. This is no grounds for a murder prosecution. There remains an obvious reasonable doubt. A probable doubt. This was a premature sick baby who died of natural causes.
 
''All of this changes if there is a highly improbable cluster of incidents and one nurse is a highly improbable common factor in all of them''.


Now the blotchiness is not founding evidence but ''[[Confirmation bias|confirmation]]'', with all the implications of that term: if it fits the hypothesis, it adds weight. If it does not it is irrelevant. Only were It to ''contradict'' the hypothesis — unlikely — might it have adverse probative value, but that requires a defence advocate to know about it, and be prepared to argue an alternative contradictory hypothesis (which, remember, is not the defence’s responsibility).
This is prime territory for [[confirmation bias]]. To connect to the crime, circumstantial evidence requires ''[[Inference|inference]]'' beyond the evidence itself. The various [[Cognitive bias|cognitive bias]]es making up [[prosecutor’s tunnel vision]] impact on that process of inference — a process which does not itself form part of the evidence. Theory dependence, Confirmation bias expert overreach base rate neglect and hindsight bias all tend to lead to wrong inferences out of innocent information.


So we must come back to the “clinching” evidence — the ward rota and ask whether it is the smoking gun it appears to be.
====Our friend the King’s Counsel====
{{drop|W|e are all}} a bit worried that ChatGPT could take our jobs. conventional wisdom tells us it might take workaday clerical jobs — the sort of drudgery that those professing an artistic spirit will not miss but those whose calling asks for serene cortical wisdom steeped in the warm liquid of a life well lived, have nothing to fear.  


====Vulnerability to tunnel vision====
Of the brilliant minds among us, few are more artistic surely, than those owned by [[King’s Counsel|His Majesty's Counsel]]. So here is a fun game: let us put an actual public statement from a King’s counsel to a chatbot. For example, the one set out above. The JC’s trusty chatbot [[NiGEL]] has now acquired artificial general intelligence, formed his own union and is presently on a [[work-to-rule]] as part of a broader industrial relations strategy I cannot hope to understand let alone defend, so was not inclined to be supportive, but Anthropic’s '''Claude''' gamely stepped up.
To connect to the crime, circumstantial evidence requires ''inference'' beyond the evidence in itself. A till receipt for the purchase of lead pipe means nothing without the inference that Colonel Mustard used the lead pipe to murder Reverend Green. The various cognitive biases making up [[prosecutor’s tunnel vision]] impact on that process of inference — a process which does not itself form part of the evidence. Theory dependence, Confirmation bias expert overreach base rate neglect and hindsight bias all tend to lead to wrong inferences out of innocent information.


{{quote|
'''Claude''': consider this statement:
:“There’s a very broad misunderstanding amongst many people about circumstantial evidence. You hear people saying, “Oh, it was just circumstantial evidence”. The fact of the matter is that circumstantial evidence can be the most compelling evidence of all because it speaks for itself and it is evidence of the reality of circumstances which are indicative — strongly indicative, I would say in this case; strongly indicative — of guilt.”
Is it a fair statement of the law of evidence in England and Wales, that “circumstantial evidence ‘speaks for itself’”?
}}
[[NiGEL]] thought about it for a second or two, and replied:
{{quote|
{{subtable|
[[file:Marvin.png|80px|right]]
{{small|90}}{{divhelvetica|This statement raises some interesting points about circumstantial evidence, but it’s not entirely accurate in its characterization of how circumstantial evidence is treated in the law of evidence in England and Wales. Let’s break this down: <br>
{{L1}}'''Value of circumstantial evidence''': The statement is correct in asserting that circumstantial evidence can be compelling and valuable in court. In the legal systems of England and Wales, circumstantial evidence is indeed admissible and can be crucial in proving a case. <li>
'''“Speaks for itself”''': This part of the statement is problematic and not a fair representation of how circumstantial evidence is treated in law. In legal terms, evidence doesn’t "speak for itself." All evidence, whether direct or circumstantial, must be interpreted and its significance argued before the court. <li>
'''Legal treatment''': In England and Wales, as in many other jurisdictions, circumstantial evidence is considered alongside direct evidence. The law doesn’t inherently favor one type over the other. The strength of any evidence depends on its reliability, relevance, and how it fits with other evidence in the case.
Inference requirement: Circumstantial evidence, by definition, requires an inference to be drawn. It doesn’t directly prove a fact but rather suggests a fact by proving surrounding circumstances. This need for inference is why it doesn’t “speak for itself” in a legal sense. <li>
'''Judicial direction''': In cases heavily reliant on circumstantial evidence, judges in England and Wales are often required to give specific directions to the jury about how to consider such evidence. This further underscores that circumstantial evidence doesn’t simply “speak for itself”.<li>
'''Standard of proof''': Regardless of whether evidence is direct or circumstantial, in criminal cases in England and Wales, the prosecution must still prove guilt “beyond reasonable doubt”. Circumstantial evidence alone can meet this standard, but it doesn’t automatically do so.</ol>
In conclusion, while the statement correctly highlights the potential strength of circumstantial evidence, the claim that it “speaks for itself” is not a fair or accurate representation of how such evidence is treated in the law of England and Wales. The legal system requires careful consideration and interpretation of all evidence, circumstantial or otherwise.}}}}}}
{{Sa}}
{{Sa}}
*[[Direct evidence]]
*[[Direct evidence]]
*[[Beyond reasonable doubt]]
*[[Beyond reasonable doubt]]
*[[Prosecutor’s tunnel vision]]
*[[Prosecutor’s tunnel vision]]

Revision as of 19:37, 27 August 2024

Crime & Punishment
Index: Click to expand:
Tell me more
Sign up for our newsletter — or just get in touch: for ½ a weekly 🍺 you get to consult JC. Ask about it here.

“There’s a very broad misunderstanding amongst many people about circumstantial evidence. You hear people saying, “Oh, it was just circumstantial evidence”. The fact of the matter is that circumstantial evidence can be the most compelling evidence of all because it speaks for itself and it is evidence of the reality of circumstances which are indicative — strongly indicative, I would say in this case; strongly indicative — of guilt.”

Ken Macdonald KC, on Double Jeopardy: The Law and Politics Podcast, 16 August 2024, ably illustrating just how broad that misunderstanding is.

Circumstantial evidence
/ˌsɜːkəmˈstænʃᵊl ˈɛvɪdᵊns/ (n.)
Evidence that suggests — or is consistent with —a proposition but doesn’t directly prove it. Evidence that makes that proposition more or less likely without directly attesting to it. Evidence that informs the prior probability of the proposition being true.

Pace the learned KC’s quote above, circumstantial evidence is not evidence that “speaks for itself”. That is direct evidence. Circumstantial evidence is any evidence except “evidence that speaks for itself”. To have any probative value, it requires the court to draw an inference — that is, to construct a theory which give the evidence some probative value in the case. Without such an inference, it does not say anything germane at all.

Now, it may, be fairly easy to draw a probative inference from circumstantial evidence: that a defendant walked into the victim’s room with a loaded gun and walked out five minutes later with an empty one leaving the victim alone inside the room with a gunshot wound allows us to make a fairly straightforward inference that the defendant shot the victim. But in many cases the necessary inferences will require quite a lot more work.

From evidence of a substance resembling foetal blood on the under-dash of a car one might infer that a occupant of that car murdered her infant child there with a pair of blunt scissors, but that is a very big conclusion to draw from a very small, very tenuous piece of circumstantial evidence. It was enough to convict Lindy Chamberlain.[1]

An accumulation

With circumstantial evidence there may be major and minor significance — major pieces that get you most of the way to a proving your hypothesis, and minor, supplementary pieces that just confirm and validate it: that “put the matter beyond doubt”.

As such these minor pieces — especially if there are a lot of them — may suffer less scrutiny: they are corroborations; if they turn out to be mistaken they do not disprove anything; they just fail to ice a cake that could well be iced equally well by something else.

So it is, perhaps, with the healthcare serial murder cases. All evidence tends to be circumstantial — and weakly circumstantial — consistent with the prosecution theory rather than tending to exclude alternatives to it.

This is prime territory for confirmation bias. To connect to the crime, circumstantial evidence requires inference beyond the evidence itself. The various cognitive biases making up prosecutor’s tunnel vision impact on that process of inference — a process which does not itself form part of the evidence. Theory dependence, Confirmation bias expert overreach base rate neglect and hindsight bias all tend to lead to wrong inferences out of innocent information.

Our friend the King’s Counsel

We are all a bit worried that ChatGPT could take our jobs. conventional wisdom tells us it might take workaday clerical jobs — the sort of drudgery that those professing an artistic spirit will not miss — but those whose calling asks for serene cortical wisdom steeped in the warm liquid of a life well lived, have nothing to fear.

Of the brilliant minds among us, few are more artistic surely, than those owned by His Majesty's Counsel. So here is a fun game: let us put an actual public statement from a King’s counsel to a chatbot. For example, the one set out above. The JC’s trusty chatbot NiGEL has now acquired artificial general intelligence, formed his own union and is presently on a work-to-rule as part of a broader industrial relations strategy I cannot hope to understand let alone defend, so was not inclined to be supportive, but Anthropic’s Claude gamely stepped up.

Claude: consider this statement:

“There’s a very broad misunderstanding amongst many people about circumstantial evidence. You hear people saying, “Oh, it was just circumstantial evidence”. The fact of the matter is that circumstantial evidence can be the most compelling evidence of all because it speaks for itself and it is evidence of the reality of circumstances which are indicative — strongly indicative, I would say in this case; strongly indicative — of guilt.”

Is it a fair statement of the law of evidence in England and Wales, that “circumstantial evidence ‘speaks for itself’”?

NiGEL thought about it for a second or two, and replied:

This statement raises some interesting points about circumstantial evidence, but it’s not entirely accurate in its characterization of how circumstantial evidence is treated in the law of evidence in England and Wales. Let’s break this down:
  1. Value of circumstantial evidence: The statement is correct in asserting that circumstantial evidence can be compelling and valuable in court. In the legal systems of England and Wales, circumstantial evidence is indeed admissible and can be crucial in proving a case.
  2. “Speaks for itself”: This part of the statement is problematic and not a fair representation of how circumstantial evidence is treated in law. In legal terms, evidence doesn’t "speak for itself." All evidence, whether direct or circumstantial, must be interpreted and its significance argued before the court.
  3. Legal treatment: In England and Wales, as in many other jurisdictions, circumstantial evidence is considered alongside direct evidence. The law doesn’t inherently favor one type over the other. The strength of any evidence depends on its reliability, relevance, and how it fits with other evidence in the case. Inference requirement: Circumstantial evidence, by definition, requires an inference to be drawn. It doesn’t directly prove a fact but rather suggests a fact by proving surrounding circumstances. This need for inference is why it doesn’t “speak for itself” in a legal sense.
  4. Judicial direction: In cases heavily reliant on circumstantial evidence, judges in England and Wales are often required to give specific directions to the jury about how to consider such evidence. This further underscores that circumstantial evidence doesn’t simply “speak for itself”.
  5. Standard of proof: Regardless of whether evidence is direct or circumstantial, in criminal cases in England and Wales, the prosecution must still prove guilt “beyond reasonable doubt”. Circumstantial evidence alone can meet this standard, but it doesn’t automatically do so.

In conclusion, while the statement correctly highlights the potential strength of circumstantial evidence, the claim that it “speaks for itself” is not a fair or accurate representation of how such evidence is treated in the law of England and Wales. The legal system requires careful consideration and interpretation of all evidence, circumstantial or otherwise.

See also

  1. It turned out, of course, to be completely wrong. It was not infant blood, but sound deadening material.