Lucy Letby: Difference between revisions

Jump to navigation Jump to search
no edit summary
No edit summary
No edit summary
Line 1: Line 1:
{{a|podcasts|{{image|grail witch|jpg|“What makes you think she’s a witch?”}}}}{{quote|
{{a|podcasts|{{image|grail witch|jpg|“What makes you think she’s a witch?”}}}}{{quote|
“We’ve found a witch. May we burn her?”
“We’ve found a witch. May we burn her?”
:— Peasant, ''Monty Python and the Holy Grail''}}
:— ''Monty Python and the Holy Grail''}}


====“There are ways of telling she’s a witch”====
====On herd minds, groupthink and narrative biases====
BBC Reporter Judith Moritz (reviewing social media posts on a ostentatiously product-placed MacBook): {{quote|
{{drop|L|ucy Letby’s case}} is in the news. Those internet citizens who have taken more than a passing interest have divided into opposing camps. There are some for whom Lucy Letby is a cold-blooded monster. Others question the safety of her criminal conviction. Those with a passing acquaintance with the case tend to suppose she must be a monster, having been convicted of it. But those who take a closer look tend quickly to gravitate to an extreme: either they are horrified by the extent of her visceral wickedness or certain, beyond a reasonable doubt, that Lucy Letby is positively innocent of all charges, and even some kind of martyred saint.
“Sparky, full of fun, popular — she looks like the life and soul of the party in these photos. I don’t know what Britain’s most prolific child killer should look like. ''I’m pretty sure it’s not this, though''.}}
{{Quote|“She comes across as — mousy; a bit ''normal'' — you can’t really marry that with the enormity of what she’s been accused of.”}}
This fits two profiles: either this is some cold, callous, monstrous psychopath — or ''a perfectly ordinary young woman''. You know — a sparky, fun, popular young woman. The life and soul of the party.


====On herd minds, groupthink and narrative bias====
These two extremes — outright innocence and guilt beyond reasonable doubt — leave a wide range of ambivalent attitudes between. Bu humans like our narratives to tell us things about the world, and a narrative that says, “huh, who knows?” is not awfully helpful. It doesn’t tell us much about the world.  
{{drop|L|ucy Letby’s case}} is in the news. Those internet citizens who have taken more than a passing interest have divided into opposing camps: a large preponderance for whom she is a cold-blooded monster and a small band who, based on advanced statistical techniques, have questioned the safety of her conviction. Those have tended to quickly spill over from scepticism about the strength of a positive case into the full-throated conviction about a negative one: they are certain, beyond a reasonable doubt, that Lucy Letby is positively innocent of all charges.


JC has his opinions, which we will get to, but the first step is to keep an open mind. Innocence and guilt beyond reasonable doubt leave a wide range of ambivalent attitudes between.
It may offer little intellectual satisfaction, but it may be the best we can reasonably expect.


Bu humans like our narratives to tell us meaningful things about the world, and that means ruling other things out. A narrative that says, “huh, who knows?” is not wildly instructive. It doesn’t tell us much about the world. It offers little intellectual satisfaction.
The system has behaved in a way which renders Lucy Letby either a monster or scapegoat. There is no middle ground, in which she is an ordinary kid, with her pluses and minuses, virtues and failings, just like the rest of us: she is either angel or devil.


But it may be the best we can reasonably expect.
Given the probabilities at play — 99% of us are neither angel or devil — giving Lucy Letby only these two choices is an injustice in itself.  


The problem with “conviction” and “innocence” narratives is that they become self-fulfilling. Once you form a view you can panel-beat a great range of subsequently occurring information so it suits your view. Especially ambivalent information that doesn’t really help one way or another.  
The problem with “conviction” and “innocence” narratives is that they become self-fulfilling: from either perspective you can panel-beat most subsequent information to suit that view. The hard-edged peripheral evidence we do have can and has been coloured through that lens.  


The mechanisms by which we do this are ''biases'' — either  [[confirmation bias]] — a well-documented logical fallacy — or its less-understood converse: [[ignore|''ignorance'' bias]],<ref>JC made this term up.</ref> whereby we ''ignore'' information that does not support our theory, or tends to contradict it.  
Here is BBC Reporter Judith Moritz, in a piece to camera, on reviewing Letby’s social media posts:{{quote|
“Sparky, full of fun, popular — she looks like the life and soul of the party in these photos. I don’t know what Britain’s most prolific child killer should look like. ''I’m pretty sure it’s not this, though''.}}And then a few moments later.{{Quote|“She comes across as mousy; a bit ''normal'' — you can’t really marry that with the enormity of what she’s been accused of.”}}Lucy Letby’s apparently vivacious personality and active social life, for example. If you have an open mind, this behaviour is ''normal''. It tells us nothing. It places Lucy Letby within a standard deviation of the mean. But once you are persuaded of her guilt it marks her out as a psychopath — ''corroborates'' and ''amplifies'' her wickedness. If you believe her to be innocent, that this information has been so rudely traduced only illustrates the single-mindedness with which our vicious system will crush an innocent, unsuspecting spirit.  


Both can serve either certainty: that Lucy Letby is a serial killer, or the victim of a grave injustice. Both standpoints are equally ''emotive''. There is no comfortable centre to hold here.
Similarly, that Lucy Letby searched online for the parents of the deceased is consistent with ''either'' breathtaking malevolence — if she is a serial killer — ''or'' affecting compassion — if she is not. But by itself, it is ''evidence'' of neither. We all Google individuals we meet in real life — even people we know we probably shouldn’t: this is perfectly normal behaviour. We are curious animals.
 
So we must remember there is  another active participant in our judgment here: our own cultural baggage. The mechanisms by which we process information are ''biases'' — [[confirmation bias]] — a well-documented logical fallacy where we frame any information to validate what we already believe — or its less-understood converse: [[ignore|''ignorance'' bias]],<ref>JC made this term up.</ref> where we tactically ''ignore'' information that does not support, or tends to contradict, our working theory.
 
Both biases are in play whether we believe Lucy Letby is a serial killer, or the victim of a grave injustice. Both standpoints are equally ''emotive''.  
 
There is no comfortable centre to hold here.
====Standpoint intersection ahoy====
====Standpoint intersection ahoy====
We are at the intersection of at least four discrete fields of intellectual enquiry here: law, medicine, statistics and ethics. They  are not commensurate — they each have their own rules, customs and institutions and authority in one does not commute to the others. In a perfect world their outcomes would converge, but the world is not perfect. There will be circumstances in which the correct legal outcome is not morally right, the correct moral outcome is not borne by the statistics, the statistics are at odds with our knowledge, and vice versa. There is little wonder good people get upset.
{{Drop|S|peaking of narratives}} there are many at play here. Criminal justice stands at the intersection of at least four discrete fields of intellectual enquiry: law, medicine, statistics and ethics. They  are not [[The Structure of Scientific Revolutions|commensurate]] — each has its own rules, customs and institutions and authority in one does not commute to the others. In a perfect world their outcomes would converge, but the world is not perfect. There will be circumstances in which the correct legal outcome is not morally right, the correct moral outcome is not borne by the statistics, the statistics are at odds with our knowledge, and vice versa. There is little wonder good people get upset.


There is even room for epistemology. You cannot but frame your understanding of the overall scenario through one or other of those prisms. Or a combination, but that is liable to lead to conflict. There is no transcendent, neutral frame of reference by which the others may be judged. Without a framework the territory is random, incoherent noise.
There is even room for epistemology. You cannot but frame your understanding of the overall scenario through one or other of those prisms. Or a combination, but that is liable to lead to conflict. There is no transcendent, neutral frame of reference by which the others may be judged. Without a framework the territory is random, incoherent noise.


For the scenario is one that unusually uncertain,  about which the prospect of consensus is unusually low.  It is not even clear that there was a wrongful killing here, let alone by whom.
For the scenario is one that unusually uncertain,  about which the prospect of consensus is unusually low.  It is not even clear that there was a wrongful killing here, let alone by whom.
====Careful of that narrative, Eugene====
And there is a more visceral narrative frame at play, too, for the way the system has behaved Lucy Letby is either a monster or a scapegoat — there is no middle ground, where she is an ordinary kid, with her pluses and minuses, virtues and failings, just like the rest of us, available to her. She is either angel or devil. Given the probabilities at play — 99% of the population are neither — this seems an injustice in itself.
The hard-edged peripheral evidence we do have can and has been coloured through that lens. Her apparently vivacious personality and active social life marks her out as a psychopath — ''corroborates''  her wickedness — or illustrates the single-mindedness with which a vicious system will crush an innocent, unsuspecting spirit. That she searched online for the parents of the deceased is consistent with either breathtaking malevolence — if she is guilty — or affecting compassion if she is not. Unless evidence can be shown that no innocent carer ever sought out her patients relatives on line, it is evidence of neither. We all Google individuals we meet in real life. This is perfectly normal behaviour.


====Substance, form and process====
====Substance, form and process====

Navigation menu