Lucy Letby: Difference between revisions

From The Jolly Contrarian
Jump to navigation Jump to search
No edit summary
Tags: Mobile edit Mobile web edit Advanced mobile edit
No edit summary
 
(23 intermediate revisions by the same user not shown)
Line 1: Line 1:
{{a|podcasts|}}==We’ve found a witch. May we burn her?==
{{a|podcasts|{{image|grail witch|jpg|“What makes you think she’s a witch?”}}}}{{quote|
BBC Reporter Judith Moritz (reviewing social media posts on a ostentatiously product-placed MacBook): {{quote|
“We’ve found a witch. May we burn her?
“Sparky, full of fun, popular she looks like the life and soul of the party in these photos. I don't know what Britain's most prolific child killer should look. I'm pretty sure it’s not this, though.}}
:— ''Monty Python and the Holy Grail''}}


This fits two profiles: either this is some cold, callous, monstrous psychopath — or ''a perfectly ordinary young woman''. You know — a sparky, fun, popular young woman. The life and soul of the party.
====On herd minds, groupthink and narrative biases====
{{drop|L|ucy Letby’s case}} is in the news. On 24 May 2024, the Court of Appeal denied Letby leave to appeal against her conviction. Neither the grounds for the appeal nor the reasons for refusal are yet public. On 10 June, her retrial for the attempted murder of “Child K” began in Manchester. But on 13 May 2024, ''New Yorker'' magazine published {{plainlink|https://wayback-api.archive.org/web/20240000000000*/https://www.newyorker.com/magazine/2024/05/20/lucy-letby-was-found-guilty-of-killing-seven-babies-did-she-do-it|''A British Nurse Was Found Guilty of Killing Seven Babies. Did she do it?''}}, a 13,000-word investigative piece by Rachel Aviv that questioned the the safety of Letby’s original convictions. The piece was loosely geo-blocked in the UK, ostensibly to avoid contempt of court during the retrial. But it is not hard to find online, and it ran unedited in the New Yorker’s UK print edition, so there may be some canny “Streisand Effect” marketing at play here too. It raises its own questions about the practicality of ''sub judice'' rules in the age of the world-wide internet, but that is a discussion for another day.


What are the percentages of serial killers with history of broken homes, physical or sexual abuse, mental illness
Those with a passing acquaintance of the case tend to suppose that, having been convicted of multiple infant murders, the case is closed and she must be a monster. She admitted everything in a note, right? But look a bit closer and the picture is complicated. The note is not the unequivocal confession it has been made out to be. There is no direct evidence. Each piece of circumstantial evidence, in isolation, is ambiguous. The strength of the case of conviction appears to have emerged from the preponderance of evidence, rather than subsisting in a particular smoking gun.


“God complex”
At this point there are two available narratives: Lucy Letby is either a person of pure, calculated evil, or the victim of a breathtaking miscarriage of justice. But these extremes leave untouched between them a vast range of ambivalent attitudes: We like our narratives to tell us things about the world, and a perspective that says, “well, it’s complicated” doesn’t tell us much about the world. It isn’t useful. So few of us occupy that space.
 
JC will advance the position that we ''should''. While it may offer little intellectual satisfaction, it may be the best we can reasonably expect.
 
The system has behaved in a way which deprives this individual of a middle ground, in which she is an ordinary kid, with her pluses and minuses, virtues and failings, just like the rest of us: neither angel nor devil. 
 
Given the probabilities at play — 99% of us are neither pure angels or devils, but somewhere along the continuum between — allowing Lucy Letby to sit at only one or other of these extremities seems an injustice in itself.
====Confirmation bias====
{{drop|T|he problem with}} “angel” and “devil” narratives is that they become self-fulfilling: once you’ve settled on one, you can panel-beat most subsequent information to suit that view. The little hard-edged peripheral evidence we do have about Lucy Letby has been coloured through that lens. For example, her social media activity. Here is BBC reporter Judith Moritz, in a piece to camera,<ref>{{Plainlink|https://www.bbc.co.uk/iplayer/episode/m001q7dl/panorama-lucy-letby-the-nurse-who-killed|''Panorama'', 18 August 2023}}</ref> on reviewing Letby’s social media posts:
 
{{quote|
“Sparky, full of fun, popular — she looks like the life and soul of the party in these photos. I don’t know what Britain’s most prolific child killer should look like — ''I’m pretty sure it’s not this, though''.}}
 
And then a few moments later:
 
{{Quote|“She comes across as — mousy; a bit ''normal'' — you can’t really marry that with the enormity of what she’s been accused of.”}}
 
If — and ''only'' if — we are already persuaded of her guilt, her vivacious personality and active social life ''notwithstanding her malign nature'' mark her out as a psychopath. It ''corroborates'' and ''amplifies'' her wickedness. 
 
If we believe her to be innocent, that she has been convicted ''despite'' her vivacious personality and active social life — what sort of serial killer is like that? — only illustrates the single-mindedness with which a vicious criminal system will crush an innocent, unsuspecting spirit.
 
If we believe neither, but hold a neutral perspective, we see this behaviour as ''perfectly'' ''normal''. It tells us nothing. It places Lucy Letby in that ordinary space, with the rest of us, within a standard deviation of the mean. There have been very, very few serial-killer nurses. We have no idea what, as a rule, they are like. In any case, normal social media activity is neither direct nor circumstantial evidence of her perpetration of the crimes with which she has been accused, or her innocence.
 
In the language of the criminal law, then, this social media activity has low “probative” content — it doesn’t prove anything — but high “prejudicial” value — it colours any existing preconceptions a jury might hold. A court may exclude this evidence if “its prejudicial effect is out of proportion to its probative value”.<ref>Section 126, Criminal Justice Act 2003, which (per explanatory notes) preserves the common law power for the court to exclude evidence where its prejudicial effect is out of proportion to its probative value. </ref>
 
Similarly, that Lucy Letby searched online for the parents of the deceased is consistent with ''either'' breathtaking malevolence — if you take it that she is a serial killer — ''or'' affecting compassion — if you take it that she is not. By itself, it is ''evidence'' of neither. We all search online for individuals we meet in real life — even people we know we probably shouldn’t: this is perfectly normal behaviour. We are curious animals.
 
These mechanisms by which we process information are ''biases'' — [[confirmation bias]] — a well-documented logical fallacy where we frame any information to validate what we already believe — or its less-understood converse: [[ignore|''ignorance'' bias]],<ref>JC made this term up.</ref> where we tactically ''ignore'' information that does not support, or tends to contradict, our working theory.
 
Both biases are in play whether we believe Lucy Letby is a serial killer, or the victim of a grave injustice. Both standpoints are equally ''emotive''.
 
There is no comfortable centre to hold here.
====Standpoint intersection ahoy====
{{Drop|C|riminal justice stands}} here at the intersection of at least four distinct fields of enquiry: law, medicine, statistics and ethics. Their perspectives are not “[[The Structure of Scientific Revolutions|commensurate]]”: each has its own rules, customs and institutions.
 
In a perfect world, they would converge, but the world is not perfect. They may conflict. There will be times where the legal outcome is not the moral one, where the moral one is not borne by the statistics, where the statistics are at odds with our knowledge, and vice versa.
 
Since we cannot but frame our understanding of the overall scenario through one or other of those prisms, we should expect dissonance, especially in difficult cases.
 
====Victims====
{{Drop|E|motions are already}} aggravated; the stakes are raised yet higher by the undoubted loss and grief of the families of lost infants. But that grief is unavoidable and attaches to the families’ loss, which is the same whatever its cause. ''That'' the families are bereaved is not at issue: the question is ''why'': Lucy Letby’s acquittal does not postpone or deny them justice for their loss: no injustice may have been done. So advocating for Lucy Letby’s innocence should be no affront to the grieving families: one can respect their unimaginable grief and, in some way seek to ameliorate it, by arguing her case.
 
====Substance, form and process====
{{Drop|S|o we must}} keep in mind the difference between the ''substantive'' “ethical” frame of reference, and in the “legal” frame of reference there is a ''substantive'' element comprising medicinal, statistical and observational information, which is then filtered through a ''formal'' framework (the legal definition of “murder”) and a ''procedural'' one (the processes one must go through and the customs one must observe to arrive at a formal legal conclusion, including the presumption of innocence, the adversarial nature of the criminal justice system, the laws of evidence, the rules of court procedure, the tactics and strategies that defence and prosecution teams adopt within that milieu to best present their case, and the "tribunals of law and fact” — judge and jury — who must ultimately settle the question. Neither judges nor jury are necessarily, ethicists, statisticians, physicians or metaphysicians.
 
Needless to say this is a highly constrained and ''artificial'' process: the stakes are high and the process has evolved to favour certainty over doubt and protect the innocent from criminal punishment. It has few of the freedoms and laxities of the “town square”, where a freer debate can, and plainly does, play out in blogposts, twitter rants, podcasts, reddit subforums, and works of investigative journalism of greater or less rigour.
 
In the town square we address different questions with different information, and much looser rules of engagement.
 
Our justice system is meant to benefit the accused in marginal cases: acquitting the occasional perpetrator is a “lesser evil” than convicting a single innocent. In the town square, the accused are afforded far less doubt.
 
But even in the courts we get it wrong sometimes.
====The medical misadventure cases====
{{Drop|I|ndeed, cases involving}} medical misadventure, where no direct evidence and which rely on expert evidence, especially as to statistics or “science”<ref>The “junk science” of “forensic odontology” (comparing bite marks), blood spatter analysis and hair microscopy are a recurring case of injustice: Chris Fabricant, ''{{Plainlink|https://www.audible.co.uk/pd/B09PF98JST?|Junk Science and the American Criminal Justice System}}''.</ref> Sally Clark, Daniela Poggiali and Lucia de Berk are but three recent examples with strikingly similar facts patterns. We should not take concerns about statistics lightly.
 
Where there is no “direct” evidence, the form and procedure becomes all the more important.
 
In Lucy Letby’s case no direct evidence definitively links her to a single murder. No direct evidence unequivocally suggests there was a ''murder'' — as opposed to misadventure, negligence or even inadvertent accident — at all. Each case, taken in isolation, could be plausibly explained as a natural death. But by the same token nor is there unequivocal evidence that any of these were not murders, nor that, if they were, Letby did not commit them.
 
The internet is polarised around two highly unlikely contingencies.
 
It is logically possible she ''did commit the murders, logically possible she did not, and logically possible she played a role in some or all of the deaths that did not amount to murder.
 
The question of whether she should be convicted comes down, at some point, to an estimation of ''probabilities''. These inform how “sure” one can be about the proposition “defendant murdered victim”.
 
These murder cases have an unusually wide range of unknowns. In isolation , we cannot say whether there was any murder at all. The deaths could have been innocent, and they could have been culpable to some legal standard short of murder (negligence, for example)
 
====Emergence====
{{Drop|T|here is a}} kind of meta-statistics at play here, too. For even if there is reasonable doubt for every individual case, the unusual repetition of cases creates its own meta narrative.
 
Roll once and get a six, and there is no surprise. That outcome was as likely as any other. Roll ''three'' sixes and it becomes a lot less probable: you would expect that only once in two hundred and sixteen times. Unusual, but nothing yet is seriously amiss. But roll ''ten'' consecutive sixes — a probability of less than one in sixty million — and you should start inspecting your die.
 
This is the essence of the prosecution case against Lucy Letby: that while each of the deaths that occurred on her shifts was in itself explainable, a sheer number of consecutive deaths on her shift were not.
 
Unlike in Sally Clark case, prosecution did not e
 
 
Each of these enquiries requires an answer “beyond reasonable doubt”. If a victim dies in the presence of a single person with a means and motive, such that if the death was intentional there is no other possible suspect, if there is a reasonable doubt as to the death being natural — even if it probably was not — there can be no conviction.
{{Quote|
“Once is happenstance. Twice is coincidence. Three times is enemy action.”
— Ian Fleming, ''Goldfinger'' (1959)}}
Here is where a sequence makes a difference. One such occurrence might be improbable, five occurrences extremely improbable, 500,
 
==So==
What are the percentages of serial killers with history of broken homes, physical or sexual abuse, and mental illness? What percentage are female?
 
====“God complex”====
Killing people is not evidence of a God complex. The basest criminal can take life. ''Bringing people back to life '' — that is evidence of a God complex.
Killing people is not evidence of a God complex. The basest criminal can take life. ''Bringing people back to life '' — that is evidence of a God complex.
==Evidence==
===Insulin “smoking gun”===
In two cases (Child F and Child L) lab tests indicating high levels of insulin without accompanying c-peptide, which is prime facie evidence of administered insulin (naturally occurring insulin is accompanied by c-peptides; artificially administered insulin is not). Insulin was not prescribed for either infant. If it was true that insulin was added without prescription this is evidence of actual human agency in these two episodes.
The defence team accepted the prosecution’s claim that insulin was added to parenteral nutrition bags and it was presented to the court as an agreed fact.<ref>{{plainlink|https://www.scienceontrial.com/post/criminal-justice-in-england-disagreeable-facts|Science on Trial}}</ref>
*'''The test in question was not reliable for factitious insulin'''. From the label:
{{quote|
“Please note that the insulin assay performed at RLUH is not suitable for the investigation of factitious hypoglycaemia.  If exogenous insulin administration is suspected as the cause of hypoglycaemia, please inform the laboratory so that the sample can be referred externally for analysis.”}}
*'''The test results seem to indicate very high levels of insulin''': 4657 pmol/L is about four times a dangerously high level in an adult.<ref>There is plenty of online angst about whether the level recorded was abnormally high or ''absurdly'' high, such that such a level had never been witnessed in medical history: let’s go with abnormally high.</ref> While, yes, this is what you might expect a murderer to try to do —
*'''Both babies recovered''': You might expect premature babies registering such high insulin levels — four times a critical level for an adult<ref>See: ''Very Well Health: Hyperinsulinema (High Insulin Levels)''[https://www.verywellhealth.com/hyperinsulinemia-is-associated-with-type-2-diabetes-1087717#:~:text=Your%20insulin%20levels%20are%20considered,could%20be%20diagnosed%20with%20hyperinsulinemia. .]</ref> — might have at least caused a fuss at the hospital. But not only did the babies make a full recovery, with no record of hypoglycemic coma, but —
*'''No-one even noticed the high insulin in their tests until 2018''': That is, three years ''after'' the babies made a full recovery. If you are looking for a [[res ipsa loquitur]] about these events, can we suggest that this is as indicative of negligence in the clinical staff administering the test, or the self-professed unreliability of the tests for detecting factitious insulin.
=== The Texas sharpshooter ===
See the {{plainlink|https://staging.d1rk7j2m6oprqr.amplifyapp.com/|TriedbyStats}} website: Over 730 shifts, with 38 “suspects” If you self-select one
=== The victim’s families ===
There are unquestionable victims here: the families.  If Lucy Letby wasn’t responsible then this was either an unavoidable accident, in which case, there is no closure, or there is another culpable explanation — an alternative murderer seems extremely implausible — but medical misadventure of some kind is not.
Difficult
=== The post-it note ===
Everyone seems to accept the notes are highly inclusive and of little evidential value.
{{Quote|“The ramblings of someone under extreme psychological pressure.”}}
==Resources==
====Online====
*{{plainlink|https://wayback-api.archive.org/web/20240000000000*/https://www.newyorker.com/magazine/2024/05/20/lucy-letby-was-found-guilty-of-killing-seven-babies-did-she-do-it|''That'' New Yorker Article}} (choose your own snapshot from the Wayback Machine)
*{{plainlink|https://mephitis.co/the-lucy-letby-case-may-in-time-be-the-story-of-the-century/|Mephitis - The Lucy Letby Case May In Time Be The Story Of The Century}}
*{{plainlink|https://staging.d1rk7j2m6oprqr.amplifyapp.com/|TriedbyStats}}
*{{plainlink|https://www.scienceontrial.com/post/criminal-justice-in-england-disagreeable-facts|The Insulin ‘Evidence’ in the Lucy Letby Trial. Criminal Justice in England: Disagreeable Facts}}
====Podcasts====
*{{plainlink|https://open.spotify.com/show/2x2kstQwsyndvK0S8OOSBZ|We need to talk about Lucy Letby}} (Peter Elston and Michael McConville podcast)
*{{plainlink|https://open.spotify.com/show/5EZDmxyDtMPeJ1laVDWuWd|The Trial of Lucy Letby}} (Daily Mail podcast)


What percentage are female
{{Sa}}
{{Sa}}
*[[Miscarriages of justice]]
*[[Miscarriages of justice]]
{{ref}}

Latest revision as of 08:13, 17 June 2024

The JC Sounds Off™
Grail witch.jpg
“What makes you think she’s a witch?”
Podcasts, publications and pop from your favourite crusty old sod.
Music: DangerboySupercheese

Published: The Montenegro SanctionTrundlers’ Progress

Podcasts: The dog in the night timeThe secret life of horns

Comments? Questions? Suggestions? Requests? Insults? We’d love to 📧 hear from you.
Sign up for our newsletter.

“We’ve found a witch. May we burn her?”

Monty Python and the Holy Grail

On herd minds, groupthink and narrative biases

Lucy Letby’s case is in the news. On 24 May 2024, the Court of Appeal denied Letby leave to appeal against her conviction. Neither the grounds for the appeal nor the reasons for refusal are yet public. On 10 June, her retrial for the attempted murder of “Child K” began in Manchester. But on 13 May 2024, New Yorker magazine published A British Nurse Was Found Guilty of Killing Seven Babies. Did she do it?, a 13,000-word investigative piece by Rachel Aviv that questioned the the safety of Letby’s original convictions. The piece was loosely geo-blocked in the UK, ostensibly to avoid contempt of court during the retrial. But it is not hard to find online, and it ran unedited in the New Yorker’s UK print edition, so there may be some canny “Streisand Effect” marketing at play here too. It raises its own questions about the practicality of sub judice rules in the age of the world-wide internet, but that is a discussion for another day.

Those with a passing acquaintance of the case tend to suppose that, having been convicted of multiple infant murders, the case is closed and she must be a monster. She admitted everything in a note, right? But look a bit closer and the picture is complicated. The note is not the unequivocal confession it has been made out to be. There is no direct evidence. Each piece of circumstantial evidence, in isolation, is ambiguous. The strength of the case of conviction appears to have emerged from the preponderance of evidence, rather than subsisting in a particular smoking gun.

At this point there are two available narratives: Lucy Letby is either a person of pure, calculated evil, or the victim of a breathtaking miscarriage of justice. But these extremes leave untouched between them a vast range of ambivalent attitudes: We like our narratives to tell us things about the world, and a perspective that says, “well, it’s complicated” doesn’t tell us much about the world. It isn’t useful. So few of us occupy that space.

JC will advance the position that we should. While it may offer little intellectual satisfaction, it may be the best we can reasonably expect.

The system has behaved in a way which deprives this individual of a middle ground, in which she is an ordinary kid, with her pluses and minuses, virtues and failings, just like the rest of us: neither angel nor devil.

Given the probabilities at play — 99% of us are neither pure angels or devils, but somewhere along the continuum between — allowing Lucy Letby to sit at only one or other of these extremities seems an injustice in itself.

Confirmation bias

The problem with “angel” and “devil” narratives is that they become self-fulfilling: once you’ve settled on one, you can panel-beat most subsequent information to suit that view. The little hard-edged peripheral evidence we do have about Lucy Letby has been coloured through that lens. For example, her social media activity. Here is BBC reporter Judith Moritz, in a piece to camera,[1] on reviewing Letby’s social media posts:

“Sparky, full of fun, popular — she looks like the life and soul of the party in these photos. I don’t know what Britain’s most prolific child killer should look like — I’m pretty sure it’s not this, though.

And then a few moments later:

“She comes across as — mousy; a bit normal — you can’t really marry that with the enormity of what she’s been accused of.”

If — and only if — we are already persuaded of her guilt, her vivacious personality and active social life notwithstanding her malign nature mark her out as a psychopath. It corroborates and amplifies her wickedness.

If we believe her to be innocent, that she has been convicted despite her vivacious personality and active social life — what sort of serial killer is like that? — only illustrates the single-mindedness with which a vicious criminal system will crush an innocent, unsuspecting spirit.

If we believe neither, but hold a neutral perspective, we see this behaviour as perfectly normal. It tells us nothing. It places Lucy Letby in that ordinary space, with the rest of us, within a standard deviation of the mean. There have been very, very few serial-killer nurses. We have no idea what, as a rule, they are like. In any case, normal social media activity is neither direct nor circumstantial evidence of her perpetration of the crimes with which she has been accused, or her innocence.

In the language of the criminal law, then, this social media activity has low “probative” content — it doesn’t prove anything — but high “prejudicial” value — it colours any existing preconceptions a jury might hold. A court may exclude this evidence if “its prejudicial effect is out of proportion to its probative value”.[2]

Similarly, that Lucy Letby searched online for the parents of the deceased is consistent with either breathtaking malevolence — if you take it that she is a serial killer — or affecting compassion — if you take it that she is not. By itself, it is evidence of neither. We all search online for individuals we meet in real life — even people we know we probably shouldn’t: this is perfectly normal behaviour. We are curious animals.

These mechanisms by which we process information are biasesconfirmation bias — a well-documented logical fallacy where we frame any information to validate what we already believe — or its less-understood converse: ignorance bias,[3] where we tactically ignore information that does not support, or tends to contradict, our working theory.

Both biases are in play whether we believe Lucy Letby is a serial killer, or the victim of a grave injustice. Both standpoints are equally emotive.

There is no comfortable centre to hold here.

Standpoint intersection ahoy

Criminal justice stands here at the intersection of at least four distinct fields of enquiry: law, medicine, statistics and ethics. Their perspectives are not “commensurate”: each has its own rules, customs and institutions.

In a perfect world, they would converge, but the world is not perfect. They may conflict. There will be times where the legal outcome is not the moral one, where the moral one is not borne by the statistics, where the statistics are at odds with our knowledge, and vice versa.

Since we cannot but frame our understanding of the overall scenario through one or other of those prisms, we should expect dissonance, especially in difficult cases.

Victims

Emotions are already aggravated; the stakes are raised yet higher by the undoubted loss and grief of the families of lost infants. But that grief is unavoidable and attaches to the families’ loss, which is the same whatever its cause. That the families are bereaved is not at issue: the question is why: Lucy Letby’s acquittal does not postpone or deny them justice for their loss: no injustice may have been done. So advocating for Lucy Letby’s innocence should be no affront to the grieving families: one can respect their unimaginable grief and, in some way seek to ameliorate it, by arguing her case.

Substance, form and process

So we must keep in mind the difference between the substantive “ethical” frame of reference, and in the “legal” frame of reference there is a substantive element comprising medicinal, statistical and observational information, which is then filtered through a formal framework (the legal definition of “murder”) and a procedural one (the processes one must go through and the customs one must observe to arrive at a formal legal conclusion, including the presumption of innocence, the adversarial nature of the criminal justice system, the laws of evidence, the rules of court procedure, the tactics and strategies that defence and prosecution teams adopt within that milieu to best present their case, and the "tribunals of law and fact” — judge and jury — who must ultimately settle the question. Neither judges nor jury are necessarily, ethicists, statisticians, physicians or metaphysicians.

Needless to say this is a highly constrained and artificial process: the stakes are high and the process has evolved to favour certainty over doubt and protect the innocent from criminal punishment. It has few of the freedoms and laxities of the “town square”, where a freer debate can, and plainly does, play out in blogposts, twitter rants, podcasts, reddit subforums, and works of investigative journalism of greater or less rigour.

In the town square we address different questions with different information, and much looser rules of engagement.

Our justice system is meant to benefit the accused in marginal cases: acquitting the occasional perpetrator is a “lesser evil” than convicting a single innocent. In the town square, the accused are afforded far less doubt.

But even in the courts we get it wrong sometimes.

The medical misadventure cases

Indeed, cases involving medical misadventure, where no direct evidence and which rely on expert evidence, especially as to statistics or “science”[4] Sally Clark, Daniela Poggiali and Lucia de Berk are but three recent examples with strikingly similar facts patterns. We should not take concerns about statistics lightly.

Where there is no “direct” evidence, the form and procedure becomes all the more important.

In Lucy Letby’s case no direct evidence definitively links her to a single murder. No direct evidence unequivocally suggests there was a murder — as opposed to misadventure, negligence or even inadvertent accident — at all. Each case, taken in isolation, could be plausibly explained as a natural death. But by the same token nor is there unequivocal evidence that any of these were not murders, nor that, if they were, Letby did not commit them.

The internet is polarised around two highly unlikely contingencies.

It is logically possible she did commit the murders, logically possible she did not, and logically possible she played a role in some or all of the deaths that did not amount to murder.

The question of whether she should be convicted comes down, at some point, to an estimation of probabilities. These inform how “sure” one can be about the proposition “defendant murdered victim”.

These murder cases have an unusually wide range of unknowns. In isolation , we cannot say whether there was any murder at all. The deaths could have been innocent, and they could have been culpable to some legal standard short of murder (negligence, for example)

Emergence

There is a kind of meta-statistics at play here, too. For even if there is reasonable doubt for every individual case, the unusual repetition of cases creates its own meta narrative.

Roll once and get a six, and there is no surprise. That outcome was as likely as any other. Roll three sixes and it becomes a lot less probable: you would expect that only once in two hundred and sixteen times. Unusual, but nothing yet is seriously amiss. But roll ten consecutive sixes — a probability of less than one in sixty million — and you should start inspecting your die.

This is the essence of the prosecution case against Lucy Letby: that while each of the deaths that occurred on her shifts was in itself explainable, a sheer number of consecutive deaths on her shift were not.

Unlike in Sally Clark case, prosecution did not e


Each of these enquiries requires an answer “beyond reasonable doubt”. If a victim dies in the presence of a single person with a means and motive, such that if the death was intentional there is no other possible suspect, if there is a reasonable doubt as to the death being natural — even if it probably was not — there can be no conviction.

“Once is happenstance. Twice is coincidence. Three times is enemy action.” — Ian Fleming, Goldfinger (1959)

Here is where a sequence makes a difference. One such occurrence might be improbable, five occurrences extremely improbable, 500,

So

What are the percentages of serial killers with history of broken homes, physical or sexual abuse, and mental illness? What percentage are female?

“God complex”

Killing people is not evidence of a God complex. The basest criminal can take life. Bringing people back to life — that is evidence of a God complex.

Evidence

Insulin “smoking gun”

In two cases (Child F and Child L) lab tests indicating high levels of insulin without accompanying c-peptide, which is prime facie evidence of administered insulin (naturally occurring insulin is accompanied by c-peptides; artificially administered insulin is not). Insulin was not prescribed for either infant. If it was true that insulin was added without prescription this is evidence of actual human agency in these two episodes.

The defence team accepted the prosecution’s claim that insulin was added to parenteral nutrition bags and it was presented to the court as an agreed fact.[5]

  • The test in question was not reliable for factitious insulin. From the label:

“Please note that the insulin assay performed at RLUH is not suitable for the investigation of factitious hypoglycaemia. If exogenous insulin administration is suspected as the cause of hypoglycaemia, please inform the laboratory so that the sample can be referred externally for analysis.”

  • The test results seem to indicate very high levels of insulin: 4657 pmol/L is about four times a dangerously high level in an adult.[6] While, yes, this is what you might expect a murderer to try to do —
  • Both babies recovered: You might expect premature babies registering such high insulin levels — four times a critical level for an adult[7] — might have at least caused a fuss at the hospital. But not only did the babies make a full recovery, with no record of hypoglycemic coma, but —
  • No-one even noticed the high insulin in their tests until 2018: That is, three years after the babies made a full recovery. If you are looking for a res ipsa loquitur about these events, can we suggest that this is as indicative of negligence in the clinical staff administering the test, or the self-professed unreliability of the tests for detecting factitious insulin.

The Texas sharpshooter

See the TriedbyStats website: Over 730 shifts, with 38 “suspects” If you self-select one

The victim’s families

There are unquestionable victims here: the families. If Lucy Letby wasn’t responsible then this was either an unavoidable accident, in which case, there is no closure, or there is another culpable explanation — an alternative murderer seems extremely implausible — but medical misadventure of some kind is not. Difficult

The post-it note

Everyone seems to accept the notes are highly inclusive and of little evidential value.

“The ramblings of someone under extreme psychological pressure.”

Resources

Online

Podcasts

See also

References

  1. Panorama, 18 August 2023
  2. Section 126, Criminal Justice Act 2003, which (per explanatory notes) preserves the common law power for the court to exclude evidence where its prejudicial effect is out of proportion to its probative value.
  3. JC made this term up.
  4. The “junk science” of “forensic odontology” (comparing bite marks), blood spatter analysis and hair microscopy are a recurring case of injustice: Chris Fabricant, Junk Science and the American Criminal Justice System.
  5. Science on Trial
  6. There is plenty of online angst about whether the level recorded was abnormally high or absurdly high, such that such a level had never been witnessed in medical history: let’s go with abnormally high.
  7. See: Very Well Health: Hyperinsulinema (High Insulin Levels).