Normal Accidents: Living with High-Risk Technologies: Difference between revisions
Amwelladmin (talk | contribs) No edit summary |
Amwelladmin (talk | contribs) No edit summary |
||
Line 1: | Line 1: | ||
{{a|devil|}}This is one of those “books that will change your life”. Well — that ''should'' change lives — that it was written in 1984 — {{author|Charles Perrow}} passed away in 2019 — suggests that, maybe it hasn’t: that the irrationalities that motivate so much of what we do are more pervasive than plainly written common sense. | {{a|devil|}}This is one of those “books that will change your life”. Well — that ''should'' change lives — that it was written in 1984 — {{author|Charles Perrow}} passed away in 2019 — suggests that, maybe it hasn’t: that the irrationalities that motivate so much of what we do are more pervasive than plainly written common sense. | ||
Charles Perrow was a sociologist who fell into the discipline of [[systems analysis]]: analysing how social structures like businesses, governments and public utilities, being loose networks of autonomous individuals, work. Perrow’s focus fell upon organisations that present specific risks to operators, passengers, innocent bystanders — nuclear and other power stations, airways, shipping lines, but the read-across to the financial systems is obvious — where a combination of [[complexity]] and [[tight coupling]] mean that periodic catastrophic accidents are not just likely, but ''inevitable''. It is the intrinsic property of a complex, tightly coupled system — not merely a function of operator error that can be blamed on a negligent employee — that it will fail catastrophically. | {{author|Charles Perrow}} was a sociologist who fell into the discipline of [[systems analysis]]: analysing how social structures like businesses, governments and public utilities, being loose networks of autonomous individuals, work. Perrow’s focus fell upon organisations that present specific risks to operators, passengers, innocent bystanders — nuclear and other power stations, airways, shipping lines, but the read-across to the financial systems is obvious — where a combination of [[complexity]] and [[tight coupling]] mean that periodic catastrophic accidents are not just likely, but ''inevitable''. It is the intrinsic property of a complex, tightly coupled system — not merely a function of operator error that can be blamed on a negligent employee — that it will fail catastrophically. | ||
If it is right, it has profound consequences for how we in complex, tightly coupled systems, should think about risk. It seems inarguably right. | If it is right, it has profound consequences for how we in complex, tightly coupled systems, should think about risk. It seems inarguably right. | ||
Line 11: | Line 11: | ||
===Normal accidents=== | ===Normal accidents=== | ||
Where you have a complex system, we should ''expect'' accidents — and opportunities, quirks and serendipities, but here we are talking about risk — to arise from unexpected, non-linear interactions. Such accidents, says Perrow, | Where you have a complex system, we should ''expect'' accidents — and opportunities, quirks and serendipities, but here we are talking about risk — to arise from unexpected, non-linear interactions. Such accidents, says Perrow, are “normal”, not in the sense of being regular or expected,<ref>In the forty-year operating history of nuclear power stations, there had (at the time of writing!) been ''no'' catastrophic meltdowns, “... but this constitutes only an “industrial infancy” for complicated, poorly understood transformation systems.” Perrow had a chilling prediction: “... the ingredients for such accidents are there, and unless we are very lucky, one or more will appear in the next decade and breach containment.” Ouch.</ref> but in the sense that it is an inherent property of the system to have this kind of accident. | ||
Are financial systems [[complex]]? About as complex as any distributed system known to humankind. Are they tightly coupled? Well, you could ask the principals of [[LTCM]], [[Enron]], Bear Stearns, Amaranth Advisors, [[Lehman]] brothers or Northern Rock, if any of those venerable institutions were still around to tell | Are financial systems [[complex]]? About as complex as any distributed system known to humankind. Are they tightly coupled? Well, you could ask the principals of [[LTCM]], [[Enron]], Bear Stearns, Amaranth Advisors, [[Lehman]] brothers or Northern Rock, if any of those venerable institutions were still around to tell you about it. But yes. Might mortage securitisations have been on Perrow’s mind? | ||
:''New financial instruments such as derivatives and hedge funds and new techniques such as programmed trading further increase the complexity of interactions. Breaking up a loan on a home into tiny packages and selling them on a world-wide basis increases interdependency.''<ref>{{br|Normal Accidents}} p. 385. This in 1999, for Pete’s sake</ref> | |||
So, financial services [[risk controller]]s take note: if your system is a complex, tightly-coupled system — and it is — ''you cannot solve for systemic failures. You can’t prevent them. You have to have arrangements in place to ''deal'' with them. These arrangements need to be able to deal with the unexpected outputs of a ''[[complex]]'' system, not the predictable effects of a merely ''[[complicated]]'' one. | So, financial services [[risk controller]]s take note: if your system is a complex, tightly-coupled system — and it is — ''you cannot solve for systemic failures. You can’t prevent them. You have to have arrangements in place to ''deal'' with them. These arrangements need to be able to deal with the unexpected outputs of a ''[[complex]]'' system, not the predictable effects of a merely ''[[complicated]]'' one. | ||
Why make the distinction between complex and complicated like this? because pre-configured | Why make the distinction between [[complex]] and [[complicated]] like this? because pre-configured safety mechanisms — think [[risk taxonomy|risk taxonomies]], [[playbook]]s, [[checklist]]s, [[neural networks]], even ~ ''cough'' ~ [[contract|contractual rights]]s may help resolve isolated failures in ''complicated'' components, but they have ''no'' chance of resolving systems failures. ''They are more likely to get in the way''. They are ''of'' the system. They are ''part'' of what has failed. Not only that: these safety mechanisms, by their existence, ''add'' complexity in the system, and when a system failure happens they can make it ''harder'' to detect what has gone wrong. | ||
===Inadvertent complexity=== | ===Inadvertent complexity=== | ||
So far, so hoopy; but here’s the rub: we can make systems and processes more or less complex and, to an extent, reduce [[tight coupling]] by careful system design and iterative improvement: | So far, so hoopy; but here’s the rub: we can make systems and processes more or less complex and, to an extent, reduce [[tight coupling]] by careful system design and iterative improvement:<ref>Air transport has become progressively less complex as it has developed. It has learned from each accident.</ref> But it is axiomatic that we can’t eliminate complexity altogether. | ||
Here is where the folly of complicated safety mechanisms comes in: adding linear safety systems to a system ''increases'' its complexity, and makes dealing with | Here is where the folly of [[complicated]] safety mechanisms comes in: adding linear safety systems to a system ''increases'' its complexity, and makes dealing with systems failures, when they occur, even harder. Not only do linear safety mechanisms exacerbate or even create their own accidents, but they also afford a degree of false comfort that encourages managers, who typically have financial targets to meet, not safety ones — to run the system harder, thus increasing the tightness of the coupling between unrelated components. That same Triple A rating that lets your risk officer catch some zeds at the switch encourages your trader to double down. ''I’m covered. What could go wrong?'' | ||
Part of the voyeuristic pleasure of Perrow’s book is the salacious detail with which he documents the sequential failures at Three Mile Island, the Space Shuttle ''Challenger'', Air New Zealand’s Erebus flight, and other disasters and near misses. The chapter on maritime collisions would be positively hilarious were it not so distressing. | |||
===“Operator error” is almost always the wrong answer=== | ===“Operator error” is almost always the wrong answer=== | ||
Line 28: | Line 31: | ||
:''But again, “operator error” is an easy classification to make. What really is at stake is an inherently dangerous working situation where production must keep moving and risk-taking is the price of continued employment.<ref>{{br|Normal Accidents}} p. 249.</ref> | :''But again, “operator error” is an easy classification to make. What really is at stake is an inherently dangerous working situation where production must keep moving and risk-taking is the price of continued employment.<ref>{{br|Normal Accidents}} p. 249.</ref> | ||
If an operator's role is simply to carry out a tricky but routine part of the system then the inevitable march of technology makes this ever more fault of design and not personnel: humans, we know, are not good computers. They are good at figuring out what to do when something unexpected happens; making decisions; exercising judgment. But they — ''we'' — are ''lousy'' at doing repetitive tasks and following instructions. As ''The Six Million Dollar Man'' had it, ''we have the technology''. We should damn well use it. | If an operator's role is simply to carry out a tricky but routine part of the system then the inevitable march of technology makes this ever more fault of design and not personnel: humans, we know, are not good computers. They are good at figuring out what to do when something unexpected happens; making decisions; exercising judgment. But they — ''we'' — are ''lousy'' at doing repetitive tasks and following instructions. As ''The Six Million Dollar Man'' had it, ''we have the technology''. We should damn well use it. | ||
If, on the other hand, the operator’s role is to manage ''complexity'' — | If, on the other hand, the operator’s role is to manage ''complexity'' — then technology, checklists and pre-packaged risk taxonomies will be of little use. Perrow’s account of the control deck at Three Mile Island is instructive: | ||
:''Besides, about this time—just four or five minutes into the accident—another more pressing problem arose. The reactor coolant pumps that had turned on started thumping and shaking. They could be heard and felt from far away in the control room. Would they withstand the violence they were exposed to? Or should they be shut off? A hasty conference was called, and they were shut off. (It could have been, perhaps should have been, a sign that there were further dangers ahead, since they were “cavitating”—not getting enough emergency coolant going through them to function properly.) In the control room there were three audible alarms sounding, and many of the 1,600 lights (on-off lights and rectangular displays with some code numbers and letters on them) were on or blinking. The operators did not turn off the main audible alarm because it would cancel some of the annunciator lights. The computer was beginning to run far behind schedule; in fact it took some hours before its message that something might be wrong with the PORV finally got its chance to be printed. Radiation alarms were coming on. The control room was filling with experts; later in the day there were about forty people there. The phones were ringing constantly, demanding information the operators did not have. Two hours and twenty minutes after the start of the accident, a new shift came on. <ref>{{br|Normal Accidents}} p. 28.</ref> | |||
This is, as Perrow sees it, the central dilemma of the complex system. The nature of normal accidents is such that they need experienced, wise operators on the ground ready to think quickly and laterally to solve unfolding problems, but the enormity of the risks | |||
Revision as of 17:53, 31 August 2020
|
This is one of those “books that will change your life”. Well — that should change lives — that it was written in 1984 — Charles Perrow passed away in 2019 — suggests that, maybe it hasn’t: that the irrationalities that motivate so much of what we do are more pervasive than plainly written common sense.
Charles Perrow was a sociologist who fell into the discipline of systems analysis: analysing how social structures like businesses, governments and public utilities, being loose networks of autonomous individuals, work. Perrow’s focus fell upon organisations that present specific risks to operators, passengers, innocent bystanders — nuclear and other power stations, airways, shipping lines, but the read-across to the financial systems is obvious — where a combination of complexity and tight coupling mean that periodic catastrophic accidents are not just likely, but inevitable. It is the intrinsic property of a complex, tightly coupled system — not merely a function of operator error that can be blamed on a negligent employee — that it will fail catastrophically.
If it is right, it has profound consequences for how we in complex, tightly coupled systems, should think about risk. It seems inarguably right.
Complex interactions and tight coupling
First, some definitions.
- Complexity: Perrow anticipates the later use of the concept of “complexity” — a topic which is beginning to infuse the advocacy part of this site — without the benefit of systems analysis, since it hadn’t really been invented when he was writing, but to describe interactions between non-adjacent subcomponents of a system that were neither intended nor anticipated by the designers of the system. Complex interactions are not only unexpected, but for a period of time (which may be critical, if the interacting components are tightly coupled) will be incomprehensible. This may be because the interactions cannot be seen, buried under second-order control and safety systems, or even because they are not believed. If your — wrong — theory of the game is that the risk in question is a ten sigma event, expected only once in one hundred million years, you may have a hard time believing it could be happening in your fourth year of operation, as the partners of Long Term Capital Management may tell you. Here even epistemology is in play. Interactions that were not in our basic conceptualisation the world, are not ones we can reasonably anticipate. These interactions were, QED, not designed into the system; no one intended them. “They baffle us because we acted in terms of our own designs of a world that we expected to exist—but the world was different.”[1]
- Linear interactions: Contrast complex interactions with much more common “linear interactions”, where parts of the system interact with other components that precede or follow them in the system in ways that are expected and planned: “if this, then that”. In a well-designed system, these will (of course) predominate: any decent system should mainly do what it is designed to do and not act erratically in normal operation. Some systems are more complex than others, but even in the most linear systems are susceptible to some complexity — where they interact with the environment.[2] Cutting back into the language of systems analysis for a moment, consider that linear interactions are a feature of simple and complicated systems, and can be “pre-solved” and brute-force computed; at least in theory. They can be managed by algorithm, or playbook. But complex interactions, by definition, cannot — they are the interactions the algorithm didn’t expect.
- Tight coupling: However complex interactions are only a source of catastrophe if another condition is satisfied: that they are “tightly coupled” — processes happen fast, can’t be turned off, failing components can’t be isolated. Perrow’s observation is that systems tend to be more tightly coupled than we realise.
Normal accidents
Where you have a complex system, we should expect accidents — and opportunities, quirks and serendipities, but here we are talking about risk — to arise from unexpected, non-linear interactions. Such accidents, says Perrow, are “normal”, not in the sense of being regular or expected,[3] but in the sense that it is an inherent property of the system to have this kind of accident.
Are financial systems complex? About as complex as any distributed system known to humankind. Are they tightly coupled? Well, you could ask the principals of LTCM, Enron, Bear Stearns, Amaranth Advisors, Lehman brothers or Northern Rock, if any of those venerable institutions were still around to tell you about it. But yes. Might mortage securitisations have been on Perrow’s mind?
- New financial instruments such as derivatives and hedge funds and new techniques such as programmed trading further increase the complexity of interactions. Breaking up a loan on a home into tiny packages and selling them on a world-wide basis increases interdependency.[4]
So, financial services risk controllers take note: if your system is a complex, tightly-coupled system — and it is — you cannot solve for systemic failures. You can’t prevent them. You have to have arrangements in place to deal with them. These arrangements need to be able to deal with the unexpected outputs of a complex system, not the predictable effects of a merely complicated one.
Why make the distinction between complex and complicated like this? because pre-configured safety mechanisms — think risk taxonomies, playbooks, checklists, neural networks, even ~ cough ~ contractual rightss may help resolve isolated failures in complicated components, but they have no chance of resolving systems failures. They are more likely to get in the way. They are of the system. They are part of what has failed. Not only that: these safety mechanisms, by their existence, add complexity in the system, and when a system failure happens they can make it harder to detect what has gone wrong.
Inadvertent complexity
So far, so hoopy; but here’s the rub: we can make systems and processes more or less complex and, to an extent, reduce tight coupling by careful system design and iterative improvement:[5] But it is axiomatic that we can’t eliminate complexity altogether.
Here is where the folly of complicated safety mechanisms comes in: adding linear safety systems to a system increases its complexity, and makes dealing with systems failures, when they occur, even harder. Not only do linear safety mechanisms exacerbate or even create their own accidents, but they also afford a degree of false comfort that encourages managers, who typically have financial targets to meet, not safety ones — to run the system harder, thus increasing the tightness of the coupling between unrelated components. That same Triple A rating that lets your risk officer catch some zeds at the switch encourages your trader to double down. I’m covered. What could go wrong?
Part of the voyeuristic pleasure of Perrow’s book is the salacious detail with which he documents the sequential failures at Three Mile Island, the Space Shuttle Challenger, Air New Zealand’s Erebus flight, and other disasters and near misses. The chapter on maritime collisions would be positively hilarious were it not so distressing.
“Operator error” is almost always the wrong answer
Human beings being system components, it is rash to blame for failure a component constitutionally disposed to fail, even when not put in a position, through system design or economic incentive — a ship’s captain being expected to work a 48-hour watch — where failure is more or less inevitable (Perrow calls these “forced operator errors”).
- But again, “operator error” is an easy classification to make. What really is at stake is an inherently dangerous working situation where production must keep moving and risk-taking is the price of continued employment.[6]
If an operator's role is simply to carry out a tricky but routine part of the system then the inevitable march of technology makes this ever more fault of design and not personnel: humans, we know, are not good computers. They are good at figuring out what to do when something unexpected happens; making decisions; exercising judgment. But they — we — are lousy at doing repetitive tasks and following instructions. As The Six Million Dollar Man had it, we have the technology. We should damn well use it. If, on the other hand, the operator’s role is to manage complexity — then technology, checklists and pre-packaged risk taxonomies will be of little use. Perrow’s account of the control deck at Three Mile Island is instructive:
- Besides, about this time—just four or five minutes into the accident—another more pressing problem arose. The reactor coolant pumps that had turned on started thumping and shaking. They could be heard and felt from far away in the control room. Would they withstand the violence they were exposed to? Or should they be shut off? A hasty conference was called, and they were shut off. (It could have been, perhaps should have been, a sign that there were further dangers ahead, since they were “cavitating”—not getting enough emergency coolant going through them to function properly.) In the control room there were three audible alarms sounding, and many of the 1,600 lights (on-off lights and rectangular displays with some code numbers and letters on them) were on or blinking. The operators did not turn off the main audible alarm because it would cancel some of the annunciator lights. The computer was beginning to run far behind schedule; in fact it took some hours before its message that something might be wrong with the PORV finally got its chance to be printed. Radiation alarms were coming on. The control room was filling with experts; later in the day there were about forty people there. The phones were ringing constantly, demanding information the operators did not have. Two hours and twenty minutes after the start of the accident, a new shift came on. [7]
This is, as Perrow sees it, the central dilemma of the complex system. The nature of normal accidents is such that they need experienced, wise operators on the ground ready to think quickly and laterally to solve unfolding problems, but the enormity of the risks
See also
References
- ↑ Normal Accidents, p. 75. Princeton University Press. Kindle Edition.
- ↑ Perrow characterises a “complex system” as one where ten percent of interactions are complex; and a “linear system” where less than one percent or interactions are complex. The greater the percentage of complex interactions in a system, the greater the potential for system accidents.
- ↑ In the forty-year operating history of nuclear power stations, there had (at the time of writing!) been no catastrophic meltdowns, “... but this constitutes only an “industrial infancy” for complicated, poorly understood transformation systems.” Perrow had a chilling prediction: “... the ingredients for such accidents are there, and unless we are very lucky, one or more will appear in the next decade and breach containment.” Ouch.
- ↑ Normal Accidents p. 385. This in 1999, for Pete’s sake
- ↑ Air transport has become progressively less complex as it has developed. It has learned from each accident.
- ↑ Normal Accidents p. 249.
- ↑ Normal Accidents p. 28.