Template:M intro crime tunnel vision: Difference between revisions

From The Jolly Contrarian
Jump to navigation Jump to search
No edit summary
No edit summary
Line 5: Line 5:
:—Abraham Maslow}}
:—Abraham Maslow}}
{{d|Prosecutor’s tunnel vision|/ˈprɒsɪkjuːtəz/ /ˈtʌnᵊl/ /ˈvɪʒᵊn/|n}}
{{d|Prosecutor’s tunnel vision|/ˈprɒsɪkjuːtəz/ /ˈtʌnᵊl/ /ˈvɪʒᵊn/|n}}
{{drop|T|he collection of}} [[bias]]es and cognitive gin-traps that can lead ''prosecutors'' — those who “prosecute” a particular theory of the world — to stick with it, however starkly it may vary from available evidence and common sense.
{{drop|T|he collection of}} biases and cognitive gin-traps that can lead ''prosecutors'' — those who “prosecute” a particular theory of the world — to stick with it, however starkly it may vary from available evidence and common sense.


So named because it is often ''literal'' prosecutors, of crimes, who suffer from it. This kind of tunnel vision has led to notorious miscarriages of justice where innocent people come to be convicted notwithstanding clear, plausible and credible alternative explanations.  
So named because it is often ''literal'' prosecutors, of crimes, who suffer from it. This kind of tunnel vision has led to notorious miscarriages of justice where innocent people come to be convicted notwithstanding clear and plausible alternative explanations for their ostensible “crimes”.  


The same tunnel vision also motivates ideologies, conspiracies and management philosophy: 360-degree [[performance appraisal]]s, [[outsourcing]], the war on drugs; the worldwide [[Anti-money laundering|AML]] military-industrial complex: are all cases where those “prosecuting” a world-view stick with it even though the weight of evidence suggests it does not work and may even be counterproductive.  
The same tunnel vision also motivates ideologies, conspiracies and management philosophy: 360-degree [[performance appraisal]]s, [[outsourcing]], the war on drugs; the worldwide [[Anti-money laundering|AML]] military-industrial complex: are all cases where those “prosecuting” the theory stick with it even though the weight of evidence suggests it does not work and may even be counterproductive.  


At the end of the “prosecutor’s tunnel” are clear but simplistic — ''misleading'' — models of a messy world. Humans have a weakness for these: we are pattern-matching, puzzle-solving animals. We are drawn to neatness. We resile from intractability as it indicates ''weakness'': that our frail human intellect has been defeated by the ineffable natural order of things.  
The “prosecutor’s tunnel” begins with clear but simplistic — ''misleading'' — models of a messy world. Humans have a weakness for these: we are pattern-matching, puzzle-solving animals. We are drawn to neatness. We resile from intractability as it indicates ''weakness'': that our frail human intellect has been defeated by the ineffable natural order of things.  
===An elegant hypothesis===
===An elegant hypothesis===
{{drop|S|ometimes the sheer}} elegance of a prosecutor’s case can crowd out our usually strong attachment to common sense and intuition that ''this cannot be right''.   
{{drop|S|ometimes the sheer}} elegance of a prosecutor’s case can crowd out common sense and the basic intuition that ''this cannot be right''.   


We have built our legal institutions to be vulnerable to this kind of crowding out. Criminal law proceeds upon [[data]] and the weight of ''evidence'' but disallows “intuition”. Hence, an asymmetry: data — evidence is better at supporting a case for what ''did'' happen than for what did ''not''. But, [[correlation|correlation and causation]]: evidence that is “consistent with” a prosecution case does not prove it: that JC owns a bicycle is ''consistent'' with his competing in the Tour de France winner; it does not make him any more likely to actually ''do'' it.
We have built our legal institutions to be vulnerable to this kind of crowding out. Criminal law proceeds upon [[data]] and the weight of ''evidence'' but disallows “intuition”. Hence, there is an asymmetry: evidence is better at saying what ''did'' happen than what did ''not''. This is especially so where there is no direct evidence that the defendant actually did what she is accused of.


Intuition’s role is relegated to underpinning the ''presumption of innocence''. A prosecutor must prove guilt; the accused need not prove ''anything'': she cannot be expected to explain what happened for the simple reason that, presuming she did not do it, she will have no better idea about it than anyone else. The jury, we hope, leans on its intuition when conjuring doubts.
Circumstantial evidence does not directly implicate a defendant but is consistent with the prosecution theory. It accumulates: if there is enough of it, and none points away from the defendant, it can tell us something. But, [[correlation|correlation and causation]]: evidence that is “consistent with” a prosecution theory does not prove it: that JC owns a bicycle is ''consistent'' with his competing in the ''Tour de France''; it does not make him any more likely to ''do'' it. Evidence can look more meaningful than it is. This is where intuition ought to be able to help us.


But experience tells us otherwise. In what follows we will look at three famous cases from the antipodes to see what can happen when there is no independent direct evidence, when intuition and common sense are relegated behind “data” and those arguing the case become afflicted with tunnel vision. Then we will look at what causes this condition.
As it is, intuition’s role is relegated to underpinning the presumption of innocence. A prosecutor must prove guilt; the accused need not prove ''anything'': she cannot be expected to explain what happened for the simple reason that and innocent person should have no better idea about it than anyone else. The jury, we hope, leans on its intuition when conjuring doubts.
 
Experience tells us otherwise. In what follows, JC takes three notorious cases from the antipodes to see what can happen when, with no direct evidence, those arguing the case become afflicted with tunnel vision, and intuition and common sense are relegated behind “data” and circumstantial evidence. Then we will look at what causes this condition.


====A ring of dust around Ayers Rock====
====A ring of dust around Ayers Rock====
{{drop|L|indy and Michael}} Chamberlain and their three children were camping at Ayers Rock in central Australia in August 1980.<ref>''{{plainlink|https://open.spotify.com/show/4sADNVGYAf0VnP6TqaBW3i|A Perfect Storm: The True Story of the Chamberlains}}'' is a fabulous accout of the whole affair.</ref> The adults were with other campers around a campfire when Lindy heard a disturbance near the tent where her infant daughter Azaria was sleeping. She went to check on the baby and thought she saw a dingo running out of the tent. When she got to the tent, the child had vanished.  
{{drop|L|indy and Michael}} Chamberlain and their three children were camping at Ayers Rock in central Australia in August 1980.<ref>''{{plainlink|https://open.spotify.com/show/4sADNVGYAf0VnP6TqaBW3i|A Perfect Storm: The True Story of the Chamberlains}}'' is a fabulous accout of the whole affair.</ref> They were relaxing with other campers around a campfire when Lindy heard a disturbance near the tent where her infant daughter Azaria was sleeping. As she went to check on the baby she thought she saw a dingo running out of the tent. When she got to the tent, the child was gone.  


Lindy raised the alarm at once, but Azaria was never found.  
Lindy raised the alarm at once. Azaria was never found.  


Dingo attacks on humans at the time were rare, and the police believed Lindy was behaving strangely. They regarded her “dingo” explanation as absurd.<ref>A common schoolyard joke at the time: Q: What is the ring of dust rising around Ayers Rock? A: The dingoes doing a lap of honour.</ref> They, and quickly thereafter the public, concluded that Lindy had murdered and disposed of her baby.
Dingo attacks are rare, and the police believed Lindy was behaving strangely. Regarding the “dingo” explanation as absurd, quickly they concluded that Lindy had murdered and disposed of her baby. Their media management was such that before long, the public believed it, too.<ref>A common schoolyard joke at the time: Q: What is the ring of dust rising around Ayers Rock? A: The dingoes doing a lap of honour.</ref>


They built their case from the little positive evidence they had: Lindy’s absence from the campfire gave her an opportunity; her strange religious beliefs the Chamberlains were Seventh-Day Adventists — gave her a motive; what appeared to be spattered infant blood in the footwell of the Chamberlain’s car provided forensic evidence and Lindy’s odd behaviour when interviewed provided corroboration.  
The police built their case from the little positive evidence they had: Lindy’s absence from the campfire, her strange religious beliefs (the Chamberlains were Seventh-Day Adventists), her odd behaviour when interviewed and critically what appeared to be spattered infant blood in the footwell of the Chamberlain’s car.  


Many aspects of the police case were highly implausible: logistically, it was almost impossible for Lindy to have murdered Azaria in the way proposed — with blunt scissors — and disposed of the body and all evidence in the five minutes available to her. Never mind how unlikely it was for a mother — let alone a devout Christian mother — to murder her own infant in cold blood.
But many aspects of the police case were highly implausible: Lindy was absent for no more than five or ten minutes, so logistically, it would have been hard to murder Azaria in the way proposed — with blunt scissors — dispose of the body and all evidence before returning to the campsite to raise the alarm. Never mind how unlikely it was for a mother — let alone a devout Christian mother — to murder her own infant in cold blood.


Nevertheless, in 1982, Lindy Chamberlain was convicted of Azaria’s murder and spent three and a half years in prison before Azaria’s matinee jacket was found, four kilometres from the campsite, at the entrance to a dingo lair. Lindy was released and pardoned but her conviction was not finally quashed until 1992.
Nevertheless, in 1982, Lindy Chamberlain was convicted of Azaria’s murder. She spent three and a half years in prison before Azaria’s matinee jacket was found, four kilometres from the campsite, at the entrance to a dingo lair. Lindy was quickly released and pardoned, but her conviction was not finally quashed until 1992.


The “blood spatter” in the footwell of the Chamberlains’ Holden Torana turned out, much later, to be a standard sound-deadening compound applied during the car’s manufacture.
The “blood spatter” in the footwell of the Chamberlains’ Holden Torana turned out, much later, to be a standard sound-deadening compound applied during the car’s manufacture.


====Satanic panic in the Garden City====
====Satanic panic in the Garden City====
{{drop|I|n 1991, Peter}} Ellis, a childcare worker at a daycare centre in New Zealand was charged with horrific abuse of several preschool children in his care.<ref>''{{plainlink|https://open.spotify.com/show/1ZHmLlciFEQ33kkSPZTtyC|Conviction: The Christchurch Civic Creche Case}}''</ref> Police alleged, on the children’s own evidence that, among other things, Ellis abducted the children en masse during the day and subjected them to bizarre rituals and acts of unthinkable cruelty and violence before returning them to the creche unobserved before their parents were due to collect them.  
{{drop|I|n 1991, Peter}} Ellis, a childcare worker at a daycare centre in New Zealand was charged with horrific abuse of several preschool children in his care.<ref>Alexander Behse and Ali Jones’  ''{{plainlink|https://open.spotify.com/show/1ZHmLlciFEQ33kkSPZTtyC|Conviction: The Christchurch Civic Creche Case}}'' is an outstanding account of the Peter Ellis case.</ref> Police alleged, on the children’s own evidence that, among other things, Ellis abducted children ''en masse'' during the day, took them across town to a flat where he subjected them to bizarre rituals and acts of unthinkable cruelty and violence before returning them to the creche unobserved before their parents were due to collect them at the end of the day.  


In 1993 Ellis was convicted on 16 counts of child sex abuse against seven children.  
In 1993 Ellis was convicted on 16 counts of child sex abuse against seven children.  


But none of the allegations was true. In total, police and social workers interviewed 118 children but presented evidence from just 20. They discarded evidence from children who did not report abuse and those whose claims were patently impossible (some claimed amputation of organs that they still possessed).  
But none of the allegations was true.  
 
In total, police and social workers interviewed 118 children but presented evidence from just 20. They discarded evidence from children who did not report abuse and those whose claims were patently impossible (some claimed amputation of organs that they still possessed).  


Therefore, the evidence put before the court — and fully disclosed to the defence — appeared more credible than it might have had it been viewed in the wider context. Police interview techniques may have encouraged the children to embellish their stories or make them up altogether.
Therefore, the evidence put before the court — and fully disclosed to the defence — appeared more credible than it might have had it been viewed in the wider context. Police interview techniques may have encouraged the children to embellish their stories or make them up altogether.
Line 47: Line 51:
Ellis, who died in 2019, was finally exonerated posthumously in 2022.  
Ellis, who died in 2019, was finally exonerated posthumously in 2022.  
====Murder in the family====
====Murder in the family====
{{drop|A|t 6:45 am}} on the morning of June 20 1994, twenty-two-year-old David Bain returned from his Dunedin paper round to find his whole family had been shot dead.<ref>''{{plainlink|https://open.spotify.com/show/3jgt4218rVMRh9OcIRu8qd|Black Hands: A Family Mass Murder}}''</ref> He did not discover this immediately: it was midwinter dark at that hour, in the deep south of New Zealand. Without switching on a light, David first went downstairs to put on a load of laundry. He later told police it was so dark he did not notice his father’s bloodstained clothes on the machine and inadvertently washed them with his own, obliterating key evidence that might have exonerated him.  
{{drop|A|t 6:45 am}} on the morning of June 20 1994, twenty-two-year-old [[David Bain]] returned from his Dunedin paper round to find his whole family had been shot dead.<ref>''{{plainlink|https://open.spotify.com/show/3jgt4218rVMRh9OcIRu8qd|Black Hands: A Family Mass Murder}}''</ref> He did not discover this immediately: it was midwinter dark at that hour, in the deep south of New Zealand. Without switching on a light, David first went downstairs to put on a load of laundry. He later told police it was so dark he did not notice his father’s bloodstained clothes on the machine and inadvertently washed them with his own, obliterating key evidence that might have exonerated him.  


Returning upstairs, David discovered his father Robin lying in the living room beside a .22 rifle with a bullet in his head. He then found his mother, two sisters and younger brother Stephen all dead in their bedrooms. Stephen appeared to have put up a fight.   
Returning upstairs, David discovered his father Robin lying in the living room beside a .22 rifle with a bullet in his head. He then found his mother, two sisters and younger brother Stephen all dead in their bedrooms. Stephen appeared to have put up a fight.   
Line 55: Line 59:
David placed an agitated call to emergency services. It was recorded and remains a part of the public record.<ref>https://www.youtube.com/watch?v=m7HsjKDSaKA</ref>  
David placed an agitated call to emergency services. It was recorded and remains a part of the public record.<ref>https://www.youtube.com/watch?v=m7HsjKDSaKA</ref>  


David told police his father, motivated by a troubled relationship with the family, must have murdered the family before writing the computer note to the absent David and turning the gun on himself.   
David told police his father, motivated by a troubled relationship with the family, must have murdered the family before typing the note on the computer to the absent David and turning the gun on himself.   


Notwithstanding David’s account, based on circumstantial evidence including bloodstains on his clothing and spectacles, his fingerprints on the rifle, minor bruises and abrasions on his body consistent with a struggle with Stephen, and the dearth of physical evidence pointing to his father, David was convicted of all five murders.  
Notwithstanding David’s account, based on circumstantial evidence including bloodstains on his clothing and spectacles, his fingerprints on the rifle, abrasions on his body consistent with a struggle with Stephen, and the dearth of physical evidence pointing to his father, David was convicted of all five murders.  


David maintained his innocence. A campaign, led by a former New Zealand rugby international, emerged to challenge David’s conviction. The campaign uncovered shortcomings, inconsistencies and oversights in the police investigation and handling of evidence.
David maintained his innocence. Joe Karam, a former New Zealand rugby international, led a campaign to challenge David’s conviction. It uncovered procedural shortcomings, inconsistencies and oversights in the police investigation and handling of evidence.


David’s case made it to the Privy Council where, twenty years after the original trial, the court quashed Bain’s convictions and ordered a retrial. David Bain was acquitted of all charges after the second trial. He remains a free man.
Twenty years after the original trial, the Privy Council quashed Bain’s convictions and ordered a retrial. After the second trial, David Bain was acquitted of all charges. He remains a free man.
====Narrative biases====
====Narrative biases====
{{drop|T|hese cases illustrate}} the problem of relying on circumstantial evidence: with no independent ''direct'' evidence, one tends to start with a hypothesis and then fit whatever secondary and forensic evidence you have into it. This is a classic opportunity for [[Prosecutor’s tunnel vision|tunnel vision]]. It can afflict those who would defend a suspect just as firmly as it can a prosecutor.
{{drop|T|hese cases illustrate}} the problem of relying on circumstantial evidence: with no independent ''direct'' evidence, one tends to start with a hypothesis and fit whatever secondary and forensic evidence you have into it, discarding whatever does not fit. This is the classic [[Prosecutor’s tunnel vision|tunnel vision]] scenario. It can afflict those who would ''defend'' a suspect just as firmly as those who prosecute them.


All kinds of theories circulated owing to the Chamberlains’ unusual religious beliefs and “odd behaviour” in the aftermath of Azaria’s disappearance. But devout Christianity is hardly a solid [[Bayesian prior|prior]] indicating murder. Nor is odd behaviour in the aftermath of psychological trauma corroborative of anything. Who would ''not'' behave oddly in those circumstances?  
All kinds of theories circulated owing to the Chamberlains’ unusual religious beliefs and “odd behaviour” in the aftermath of Azaria’s disappearance. But devout Christianity is hardly a solid [[Bayesian prior|prior]] indicating a tendency to murder. Nor is “odd behaviour” in the aftermath of a mother’s most extreme psychological trauma. Who would ''not'' behave oddly in those circumstances?  


That ''anyone'' could bring themselves to cold-bloodedly murder a nine-week-old baby is hard to imagine. That the child’s own mother would is, in the absence of compelling evidence, ''preposterous''. To even start with this theory there must be compelling grounds pointing to this highly implausible scenario over all others — if not credible eye-witness evidence, then a documented history of violence, behavioural volatility or psychiatric illness grave enough to overthrow the strong human instinct to protect vulnerable infants. Lindy Chamberlain had no such history.
That ''anyone'' could bring themselves to cold-bloodedly murder a nine-week-old baby is hard to imagine. Statistically, it is highly improbable. That the child’s own mother would is, in the absence of compelling evidence, ''preposterous''. To even start with this theory you must surely have compelling grounds to believe it over all other possibilities — if not credible eye-witness evidence, then a documented history of violence, behavioural volatility or psychiatric illness grave enough to overthrow the strong human instinct to protect vulnerable infants. Lindy Chamberlain had no such history.


If there is ''any'' plausible alternative explanation, there must therefore be a reasonable doubt. It need not be a better explanation than the prosecution case: just not out of the question. [[Lindy Chamberlain]] provided one: a dingo snatching the child might have been unprecedented, but it was not physically impossible. There were dingoes in the area. They are predators. They are strong enough to carry away a human infant. A dingo was no less likely than a new mother noiselessly murdering her own infant just yards from a group of independent witnesses. That ought to have been the end of it.
If there is ''any'' plausible alternative explanation for the baby’s disappearance, ''there must have been a reasonable doubt''. It need not be more probable than the prosecution case: just ''not out of the question''. [[Lindy Chamberlain]] provided one: a dingo snatching the child might have been unprecedented, but it was possible. There were dingoes in the area. They are predators. They are strong enough to carry away a human infant. A dingo was no less likely than a new mother noiselessly murdering her own infant just yards from a group of independent witnesses. That ought to have been the end of it.


Likewise, what [[Peter Ellis]] was alleged to have done is ''extraordinarily'' improbable. There are few documented cases of ritualistic abuse on that scale anywhere in the world. There are none in New Zealand. To do it with no adult witnesses, no one noticing the absent children and for none of the children to bear any trace of their supposed injuries makes it even less likely.  
Likewise, what [[Peter Ellis]] was alleged to have done is ''extraordinarily'' improbable. There are few documented cases of ritualistic abuse on that scale anywhere in the world. There are none in New Zealand. For such a thing to have happened without any prior evidence of such behaviour, with no adult witnesses, no one noticing the absent children and for none of the children to bear any trace of their supposed injuries makes it even less likely.  


And there was a plausible alternative: ''nothing happened at all''. All that was required for that to be true was for preschool children, perhaps at the prompt of interviewers already in the grip of [[prosecutor’s tunnel vision]], to make things up. By comparison with “untraceable, unwitnessed, wide-scale ritual satanic abuse”, “children exercising their imaginations to please adults” ''is not improbable''.  
And there was a plausible alternative: ''nothing happened at all''. All that was required for that to be true was for preschool children, perhaps at the prompt of interviewers already in the grip of [[prosecutor’s tunnel vision]], to make things up. By comparison with “untraceable, unwitnessed, wide-scale ritual satanic abuse”, “children exercising their imaginations to please adults” ''is not improbable''.  
Line 77: Line 81:
It is different for David Bain. While it is true that familicide is extremely rare and, therefore, absent [[Bayesian prior|prior]] evidence, highly improbable, there is no question that the Bain family were murdered. The only question was ''by whom''.  
It is different for David Bain. While it is true that familicide is extremely rare and, therefore, absent [[Bayesian prior|prior]] evidence, highly improbable, there is no question that the Bain family were murdered. The only question was ''by whom''.  


On [[David Bain]]’s own theory, only two people could have done it: his father and himself. It was, therefore, ''definitely'' familicide: the abstract improbability of that explanation is therefore beside the point. The probability that David was responsible is therefore greatly higher: before considering any further evidence there is a 50% chance he was responsible.  
On David’s own theory, only two people could have done it: his father and himself. It was, therefore, ''definitely'' familicide: the abstract improbability of that explanation is therefore beside the point. The probability that David was responsible is therefore greatly higher: before considering any further evidence there is a 50% chance he was responsible.  


And a lot of the further evidence pointed in his direction. To ''not'' be the murderer, on his own evidence, David would have been ''extremely'' unlucky — forgetting to turn on the light, accidentally disposing of exculpatory evidence, having incriminating injuries he could not explain — while no such evidence pointed to Robin. David’s defenders had their own [[tunnel vision]], against this context focusing narrowly on the provenance of each piece of evidence, identifying potential shortcomings in its chain of custody and question-marks over the manner of its collection, throwing up the possibility that it ''might'' have an innocent explanation without explaining what that explanation might be, and disregarding the wider context of the whole case.
And a lot of the further evidence pointed in his direction. To ''not'' be the murderer, on his own evidence, David would have been ''extremely'' unlucky — forgetting to turn on the light, inadvertently disposing of exculpatory evidence, having incriminating injuries he could not explain — while no such evidence pointed to Robin. David’s defenders had their own [[tunnel vision]], focusing narrowly on the provenance of each piece of incriminating evidence, identifying formal shortcomings in its value as evidence: questioning the manner of its collection, the chain of custody, raising ''possibilities'' of innocent explanations without evidence to support that alternative, and disregarding the wider context of the whole case.


Now, David Bain was acquitted of all charges. On the evidence, the jury could not rule out the ''possibility'' that Robin Bain was responsible. Not being satisfied beyond reasonable doubt that David was the perpetrator, he was correctly acquitted at law. But it remains highly likely that David ''was'' the perpetrator.<ref>Christchurch Journalist Martin Van Beynen’s fantastic podcast ''{{plainlink|https://interactives.stuff.co.nz/blackhands/not-guilty/|Black Hands}}'' compellingly makes this case.</ref> As a piece of judicial procedure, the comparison between Bain’s case and those of Ellis and Chamberlain is stark.  
Now, David Bain was acquitted of all charges. On the evidence, the jury could not rule out the ''possibility'' that Robin Bain was responsible. Not being satisfied beyond reasonable doubt that David was the perpetrator, he was correctly acquitted at law. But it remains ''likely'' that David ''was'' the perpetrator.<ref>Christchurch Journalist Martin Van Beynen’s fantastic podcast ''{{plainlink|https://interactives.stuff.co.nz/blackhands/not-guilty/|Black Hands}}'' compellingly makes this case.</ref> As a piece of judicial procedure, the comparison between Bain’s case and those of Ellis and Chamberlain is stark.
====Upstanding citizen turns master criminal. Does well.====
Prosecutor’s tunnel vision cases often involve previously law-abiding citizens suddenly committing fiendish crimes without leaving direct evidence to implicate themselves beyond an absent [[Aleebee|alibi]].  


Prosecutor’s tunnel vision cases often involve previously law-abiding citizens suddenly committing fiendish crimes without leaving direct evidence to implicate themselves beyond their absent alibi. Ostensibly, Lindy Chamberlain managed this. So, ostensibly, did Peter Ellis. David Bain did not.  
Now JC is told that committing violent crimes without leaving any incriminating evidence is ''extremely'' hard. Especially in a controlled environment like a daycare centre or a hospital. Serial criminals ''can'' operate in these environments — Harold Shipman — but they need to be very careful: over time they will hone their techniques and perfect a ''modus operandi'', acquiring a ghoulish sort of ''[[metis]]''.  


Now JC is told that committing violent crimes without leaving any incriminating evidence is ''extremely'' difficult. Especially in a controlled environment like a daycare centre or a hospital. Serial criminals can operate in these environments, but they need to be good: they will hone their techniques and modus operandi as they go, acquiring a ghoulish sort of ''[[metis]]''. We should not expect the same flawless execution from first-timers. From hitherto “law-abiding citizens” we should expect slip-ups, giveaways, red flags and smoking guns. Their absence, again, should tell us something. It ''reduces'' the prior probability of foul play. If it is plausible that no crime was committed at all, an absence of incriminating evidence should tell us something.
We should not expect the same flawless execution from first-timers. From hitherto “law-abiding citizens” are learning the ropes we should expect to see slip-ups, giveaways, red flags and smoking guns.  
 
Their absence, again, should tell us something. It ''reduces'' the prior probability of foul play. If it is plausible that no crime was committed at all, an absence of incriminating evidence should tell us something.
 
For Lindy Chamberlain there was no such incriminating evidence. Nor for Peter Ellis. But for David Bain there was.  


====Standards of proof====
====Standards of proof====
{{drop|T|he prosecution’s standard}} of proof is, in theory, high: ''beyond reasonable doubt''. It isn’t clear that quite achieves what it is meant to. Courts have moved to dumb it down: that time-honoured phrase has been discarded and juries are directed to convict only if they are “sure”. While this is meant to mean the same thing, not all are persuaded that is how juries understand it.<ref>{{Plainlink|https://www.newlawjournal.co.uk/content/dreaded-questions-doubtful-answers-the-trouble-with-sure-|New Law Journal: The Trouble With “Sure”}}</ref> And there is some reason to think that juries start with a presumption that the accused is guilty at least to the balance of probabilities: assuming the police acted in good faith, why else would the defendant be in the dock?
{{drop|T|he prosecution’s standard}} of proof is, in theory, high. Courts have discarded the time-honoured phrase ''beyond reasonable doubt'' and moved to dumb it down: these days, juries are directed to convict only if they are “sure”. This is meant to mean the same thing, but not all are persuaded that is how juries understand it.<ref>{{Plainlink|https://www.newlawjournal.co.uk/content/dreaded-questions-doubtful-answers-the-trouble-with-sure-|New Law Journal: The Trouble With “Sure”}}</ref>  


But a scenario where tendentious data may be introduced in support of guilt but there is a total ''lack'' of “data” supporting exoneration — only the intuition that it seems ''highly unlikely'' that such a person should do such a thing — may lead to that confusion. Lindy Chamberlain was convicted of her own daughter’s murder, with a pair of blunt scissors, on the evidence of bloodlike spatter in the footwell of her husband’s car. The intuition that a sane mother is most unlikely to brutally murder her own nine-week-old child at all, let alone with an improvised weapon and without warning or provocation was not before the court. Somehow the jury was persuaded not just that she did it, but that there was no plausible alternative explanation.
There is some reason to think that juries start with an ad hoc presumption that a defendant is ''likely'' to be guilty, at least to the balance of probabilities: if the police were competent and acted in good faith, why else would she be in the dock?


[[JC]] draws upon ''{{plainlink|https://media.law.wisc.edu/m/2fjzd/findley_scott_ssrn_copy-1.pdf|The Multiple Dimensions of Tunnel Vision in Criminal Cases}}'' by Keith Findley and Michael Scott in the Wisconsin Law Review (2006) and {{author|Robert Cialdini}}’s {{br|Persuasion}}. To some extent also the madness of crowds and Jon Haidt’s {{br|The Righteous Mind}}. The lesson we draw is that ''we are not as rational as we like to think'' and ''data is never the whole story''.
Where there is only ''tendentious'' data supporting guilt and a total ''lack'' of “data” supporting innocence —  what evidence could there be that you did not do something that did not happen? — there are grounds for confusion here.


It may describe ''all'' view-forming of a “conviction” kind. They are like political and religious views in that, once they take root, they are not easily displaced.
Lindy Chamberlain was convicted of her own daughter’s murder, with a pair of blunt scissors, on the (tendentious) evidence of blood in the footwell of the family car.  


The “wrongful conviction” cases are bracing because, with hindsight, a better narrative and having taken a different cognitive path to the prosecutors, it is so hard to understand how they got there, or why they persisted with such plainly untenable views. If we treat prosecutor’s tunnel vision as a variety of political or even religious conviction, we can see better how “prosecutors” can be so energetic in their maintenance of a bad [[model]]. It perhaps explains the gruesome in-house performance in the {{poh}}.
The intuition that “a sane mother is most unlikely to brutally murder her own nine-week-old child at all, let alone with an improvised weapon and without warning or provocation” was not before the court. The jury did not hear this. Somehow the jury was persuaded not just that she did murder her child, but that there was no plausible alternative explanation for the child’s disappearance.


Prosecutors need not be ''literal'' prosecutors: campaigners for innocence, and conspiracy theorists suffer at the hands of the same collection of cognitive traps. Both sides of the public conversation about [[Lucy Letby]] are similarly afflicted with tunnel vision: hence, allegations of conspiracy from both sides.
==The three phases of prosecutor’s tunnel vision==
So what is “prosecutor’s tunnel vision”, then and how does it come about?
[[JC]] draws upon ''{{plainlink|https://media.law.wisc.edu/m/2fjzd/findley_scott_ssrn_copy-1.pdf|The Multiple Dimensions of Tunnel Vision in Criminal Cases}}'' by Keith Findley and Michael Scott in the Wisconsin Law Review (2006) and to a smaller extent {{author|Robert Cialdini}}’s {{br|Persuasion}}. The lessons are two-fold:
{{quote|''We are not as rational as we like to think'' and <br>''Data is never the whole story''.}}


==The three phases of tunnel vision==
Tunnel vision may afflict those with ''any'' kind of a “conviction” opinion: the behaviours strongly resemble those of people holding passionate religious and political persuasions. Once they take root, they are not easily displaced. If we treat prosecutor’s tunnel vision as a type of “emotional conviction”, we can see better how “prosecutors” can be so energetic in defending a bad mental model.  
Tunnel vision has three phases: first, the background conditions arise to make us ''vulnerable'' to tunnel vision in the first place; second, those that push us into a given tunnel; the third, those cognitive artefacts that ''keep'' us there.  


Call these “setting out”, “getting there” and “staying there”.
Tunnel vision has three phases: first, the enabling background conditions that make us ''vulnerable'' to tunnel vision; second, the pathways ''into'' a given tunnel; third, the cognitive biases that ''keep'' us there.  


In order of appearance:
====Background conditions====
 
====Background====
{{Drop|C|ertain dispositions, biases}} and miscellaneous psychological tics come together to create the conditions for tunnel vision to swamp an earnestly-held narrative:
{{Drop|C|ertain dispositions, biases}} and miscellaneous psychological tics come together to create the conditions for tunnel vision to swamp an earnestly-held narrative:


=====The “anchoring” effect=====
=====The “anchoring” effect=====
When making decisions we “anchor” our expectations on the first piece of information we get, then recalibrate as we go, not against some abstract sense of rectitude, but ''by reference to our original anchor''. That anchor disproportionately influences our assessment of later facts.   
When making decisions we “anchor” our expectations on the first information we get. We then recalibrate not against an abstract measure of value, but ''by reference to our original anchor''. Our anchor disproportionately influences our assessment of subsequent facts.   


Hence, the “discount sticker” in a car showroom: you are already getting a great deal, and you haven’t started haggling!<ref>Anchoring is relatively well documented. Kahneman and Tversky asked subjects to spin a wheel of fortune and, after spinning, to estimate the percentage of African nations in the UN. Those who landed on a higher number gave significantly higher estimates than those who landed on a lower number.</ref>
=====Overconfidence about adjacent fields=====
 
=====Overconfidence in adjacent fields=====
[[Subject matter expert]]s tend to overestimate their judgment of subtle problems, especially those ''adjacent'' to their expertise and the overall significance of matters within their expertise.  Overconfident subject matter experts are less likely to consider alternative models, explanations, theories or evidence, let alone contradictory ones.
[[Subject matter expert]]s tend to overestimate their judgment of subtle problems, especially those ''adjacent'' to their expertise and the overall significance of matters within their expertise.  Overconfident subject matter experts are less likely to consider alternative models, explanations, theories or evidence, let alone contradictory ones.


=====“To a man with a hammer...”=====
=====“To a man with a hammer...”=====
You don’t enlist in the army hoping never to shoot a gun. The police show up for work to detect ''crime'', and prosecutors to ''prosecute'' it. They are primed this way, as are we all: to be ''useful''; for their roles to be ''important'' and to ''make a difference''. We tell ourselves archetypal stories: the dogged sleuth who smelt a rat and stuck at it over the objections of her superiors — despite Sarge’s threats of a career spent issuing parking tickets and overcame the shadowy machinations of unseen malign forces. There are no archetypes about conspiracy-obsessed geeks who hound innocent prisoners to their graves.
You don’t enlist in the army hoping never to shoot a gun. The police show up for work to detect ''crime'', and prosecutors to ''prosecute'' it. They are primed this way, as are we all: to be ''useful''; for their roles to be ''important'' and to ''make a difference''. Our aspiration is to find a crime to prosecute. Those who would deter us from that stance may seem like part of the problem.
 
We tell ourselves archetypal stories: the dogged cop who sticks at her hunch despite Sarge’s threat to see out her career issuing parking tickets and overcomes the shadowy malign forces to save the day for righteousness and the American way. This is how the lead prosecutor of the Central Park Five saw herself.
 
We do not tell ourselves stories where we are conspiracy-obsessed geeks who are hounding innocent citizens to the electric chair.


=====Role pressure=====
=====Role pressure=====
Law enforcement agencies will be under pressure to get results. Curiously, this may lead to missed opportunities: notoriously, West Yorkshire police repeatedly missed Peter Sutcliffe despite interviewing him several times because he didn’t match the profile they had built, which was based on recording from a hoaxer. Their theory was that the suspect would have a wearside accident: Sutcliffe was a yorkshireman.
Law enforcement agencies will be under pressure to get results. This may lead to missed opportunities: notoriously, despite repeatedly interviewing him, police overlooked Yorkshire Ripper Peter Sutcliffe, a Yorkshireman, because his accent didn’t match their profile of a man with a Wearside accent, based on a voice recording which turned out to be a hoax.


====Getting there====
====Getting there====
{{Drop|O|nce you are}} safely anchored with your hammer and have started wandering around the house looking for nails, there should still be scope for falsification of your operating theory. But again, psychological biases can override the dispassionate application of cool logic.
{{Drop|O|nce you are}} anchored, equipped with a hammer and have started wandering around the house looking for nails, there should still be scope to falsify your operating theory. But again, psychological biases can override the dispassionate application of cool logic.


=====Extrapolation=====
=====Extrapolation=====
Especially vulnerable are [[subject matter expert]]s. We are natural problem-solvers and model builders and we will easily slip beyond our brief and intrude into matters where we have little experience. A statistician can give us a compelling account of the Bayesian probabilities, but when she strays into the causes of elevated insulin readings in a sample containing an apparently significant cluster of readings. Likewise, a medical expert may opine ''that'' the insulin readings are elevated beyond what would usually be expected, but the forensic question of ''who or what caused the excess insulin levels'' is a question of forensics and not something a diabetes specialist has any better idea about than anyone else.  
[[Subject matter expert]]s are prone to ''extrapolate''. We are natural problem-solvers and model builders. We slip easily beyond our brief and intrude into matters where we have little experience. A statistician can give us a compelling account of the Bayesian probabilities, the forensic question of ''who or what caused the excess toxins'' is a question of forensics and not something a statistician has a better idea about than anyone else.  


=====Precedent: bad heuristics=====
=====Precedent: bad heuristics=====
The greater the expertise, the more grooved the expectations, the stronger the [[heuristic]], the greater our temptation to take that shortcut and ''presume'' that this is “one of those” cases. Often the subject matter experts model will be right: if so this heuristic is a handy, efficient shortcut. In the rare case that presents one way but is an exception, it can be dangerous. Heuristics are excellent, efficient devices (as [[Gerd Gigerenzer]] notes, they help us to catch balls without needing to perform differential equations), but when the model is wrong they can lead to trouble.
The greater the expertise, the more grooved the expectations, the stronger the [[heuristic]], the greater our temptation to take that shortcut and ''presume'' that this is “one of those” cases. Where it is, the [[heuristic]] is a handy shortcut to the right answer. In the rare case where it is not, it can be dangerous. Heuristics are excellent, time-saving devices but when the model is wrong they can lead to trouble.
=====Base rate neglect=====
=====Base rate neglect=====
“Base rate neglect” — also known as the prosecutor’s fallacy — is our natural tendency of to ignore the “base rate” of a phenomenon in the population and instead focus on “individuating” information that pertains to the specific case in front of us.  
''Lawyers are not natural statisticians''. “Base rate neglect” — the “prosecutor’s fallacy” — is the natural tendency to ignore the “base rate” of a phenomenon in the population and instead focus on “individuating” information that pertains to the specific case in front of us. Here Lindy Chamberlain and Peter Ellis can be contrasted with David Bain.


If, statistically, a certain test has a 1/1000 chance of yielding a “false positive” for a given illness, but the general prevalence of that illness in the population is 1/100,000 then for every one true positive result, we should still expect 100 false positives. Worth remembering if you are diagnosed with a rare illness!
Be careful with statistics about extremely rare events.


The same principle holds for criminal offending: if there is a 1/342,000,000 chance that “so many suspicious deaths could have occurred with the same nurse on duty by sheer chance” it may seem that the fact one nurse was in fact on duty for all those suspicious deaths is damning. But this is to ignore the base rate: How many health professionals are there in the world with no criminal history, motive or mental illness who murder multiple patients?
Say a certain test gives a correct result 999 times out of 1,000. That is, it only yields one “false positive” result in a thousand tests. It is tempting to assume that a positive result is conclusive. But if the general rate in the population of the condition it is testing for — the “base rate” — is only one case in 100,000 then for every single ''true'' positive result, you should still expect 100 ''false'' positives.<ref>Assume you test 100,000 people. At a 99.9% accuracy rate, you will expect 99,900 correct results, and 100 false ones. But in that sample of 100,000 you would only expect 1 actual case of the condition. So if you are tested and receive a positive result, you have a 1 in 100 chance that it is a true result.</ref>


For the odds to be even with sheer chance — that is the “balance of probabilities”, remember, a long way short of “beyond reasonable doubt” — there would need to be ''twenty-three''. There are not twenty-three such serial killers in the world.
The same principle holds for criminal offending: if there is, say, a 1/342,000,000 chance that “so many suspicious deaths could have occurred with the same nurse on duty by sheer chance” and one nurse was in fact on duty for all those suspicious deaths, it may seem utterly damning. But this is to ignore the base rate of ''how many people are there in the world who murder multiple patients?''


Yet “one in three-hundred and forty-two million” was the figure that convicted Dutch nurse Lucia de Berk of serial murder. Even if this figure had been correct, sheer chance was still the far likelier explanation.  
On a planet with eight billion people, for the odds of our nurse being a serial killer to as high 1/342,000,000 there would need to be ''twenty-three''. There do not appear to be that many hospital serial killers in the last generation.  


It turned out the statistics were in any case wrong: the probability of her shift patterns coinciding by chance was reassessed as being more like one in twenty-five. For the odds of serial murder to be even with that, there would need to be 320 ''million'' hospital serial killers.  
Yet “one in three-hundred and forty-two million” was the figure that convicted Dutch nurse Lucia de Berk of serial murder. Had this estimate been correct (it turned out to be a wild underestimate) sheer chance was ''still'' a likelier explanation.<ref>It turned out the statistics were in any case wrong: the probability of her shift patterns coinciding by chance was reassessed as being more like one in twenty-five. De Berk’s acquittal was overturned in 2010.</ref>


Observers might note the similarities between this case and a British case that is currently in the news.
=====Confirmation bias=====
=====Confirmation bias=====
All observation is theory-dependent: scientists must first have a theory before they can gather evidence to test it: otherwise, how do they know what evidence to look for?  
All observation is theory-dependent: scientists must first have a theory before they can gather evidence to test it: otherwise, how do they know what evidence to look for?  
Line 151: Line 162:
Having picked a bad [[heuristic]], we tend to seek out, interpret, and best remember information that confirms it. We may overweight evidence that supports our theory and disregard or minimise anything that contradicts it.
Having picked a bad [[heuristic]], we tend to seek out, interpret, and best remember information that confirms it. We may overweight evidence that supports our theory and disregard or minimise anything that contradicts it.


Convinced that Lindy Chamberlain had murdered her infant daughter Azaria, Police searched high and low for blood, eventually finding some splattered over the footwell of her husband’s car. This was crucial evidence in her conviction turned out to be sound-deadening material containing iron oxide that was present on all cars of that model.
Convinced that Lindy Chamberlain had murdered her infant daughter Azaria, Police searched high and low for blood, eventually finding something resembling infant blood splattered over the footwell of her husband’s car. It turned out to be sound-deadening material containing iron oxide.


====Selective information processing====
====Selective information processing====
Focusing on certain pieces of evidence while ignoring others. Prosecutors might only present evidence that strengthens their case and neglect exculpatory evidence that could help the defence. Peter Ellis’ prosecutors interviewed twenty or more children. Some gave plainly preposterous accounts of what went on. They were not called to give evidence and their statements were considered irrelevant and therefore were not all made available to the defence.
Focusing on certain pieces of evidence while ignoring others. Prosecutors might only present evidence that strengthens their case and neglect exculpatory evidence that could help the defence. Peter Ellis’ prosecutors interviewed one hundred and eighteen children. Many denied all suggestion of abuse. Some gave plainly preposterous accounts of what went on. They were not called to give evidence. Their statements do not appear to have been fully disclosed to the defence.


====Groupthink====
====Groupthink====
Thinking or making decisions as a group in a way that discourages creativity or individual responsibility: Prosecutors might conform to the prevailing opinion within their office, stifling dissenting views and critical analysis of the case. See also [[Dan Davies]]’ idea of  “[[accountability sink]]s”. {{poh}} is perhaps the archetypal example of groupthink.
Thinking or making decisions as a group in a way that discourages creativity or individual responsibility: Prosecutors might conform to the prevailing opinion within their office, stifling dissenting views and critical analysis of the case. See also Dan Davies’ idea of  the “[[accountability sink]]s” within an organisation. The {{poh}} is perhaps the archetypal example of groupthink amongst a group of prosecuting lawyers.


====Reductionism====
====Reductionism====
Drilling deep into technical details that, by themselves, and shorn of all context, seem to lead to one conclusion — especially one you are already [[anchor]]ed to — notwithstanding the wider picture making the hypothesis unlikely. Especially in cases with no direct evidence, there is a great risk of this.  
Immersing into technical details that, by themselves and shorn of all context, seem to lead to one conclusion — especially one to which you are already [[anchor]]ed — notwithstanding the wider picture making the hypothesis unlikely. Especially in cases with no direct evidence, there is a great risk of this.  


Prosecutors’ focus on “blood”  sprayed up in the footwell of the Chamberlains car led them to a theory that Azaria was murdered there, despite no evidence supporting the theory, and quite a lot — principally, the lack of time for Lindy Chamberlain to do any such thing. The prosecution case started with “murder in the car” as the anchoring evidence, and hypothesised a whole story around it, for which there was no supporting evidence but also no contradiucting evidence, so it was “possible”. There is a ''lot'' of this in the Lucy Letby case, on both sides.


==Staying there==
==Staying there==
Once we are in a tunnel, there are cognitive biases that prevent us from finding our way out.
==== Hindsight bias and the reiteration effect ====
==== Hindsight bias and the reiteration effect ====
In hindsight, people tend to think an eventual outcome was inevitable, or more likely or predictable, than they might have before it happened. “What is the chance that that nice woman you met at the campsite just now will, in three hours, brutally murder her own nine-week old infant?” versus “Given that this nine-week old child has disappeared from the campsite, and the police suspect the mother of foul play, what is the prospect that her mother brutally murdered the child?”
In hindsight, people tend to think an eventual outcome was inevitable or more likely than they might have before it happened. “What is the chance that that nice woman you met at the campsite just now will, in three hours, brutally murder her own nine-week-old infant?” versus “Given that this woman’s nine-week-old infant has disappeared from the campsite, and the police suspect her of foul play, what is the change that she brutally murdered her own child?”


Through “hindsight bias” we project new knowledge (of actual outcomes) onto our knowledge of the past (observed behaviour), without realising that the perception of the past has been tainted by the subsequent information.
Through “hindsight bias” we project knowledge of actual outcomes onto our knowledge of the observed behaviour in the past, without realising that the perception of the past has been tainted by the subsequent information.


Once a person becomes a prime suspect and prosecutors arrive at an outcome in their own determination of who ''they'' believe is guilty — hindsight bias suggests that, upon reflection, the suspect was the inevitable and likely suspect from the beginning. Evidence is malleable in light of this “realisation”.  
Once a person becomes a prime suspect hindsight bias suggests that, upon reflection, the suspect was the inevitable and likely suspect from the beginning. Evidence is malleable in light of this “realisation”.  


This is compounded by a “reiteration” effect. Our confidence in a theory increases the more we hear it, independent of its truth or falsity. The longer that police, prosecutors and witnesses live with a conclusion of guilt, the more entrenched their conclusion becomes, and the more obvious it appears that all evidence pointed to that conclusion from the very beginning. This “reiteration effect” makes it increasingly difficult for police and prosecutors to consider alternative perpetrators or theories of a crime.
There is also a “reiteration” effect. Our confidence in a theory increases the more we hear it, independent of its validity. The longer that police, prosecutors and witnesses live with the conclusion of guilt, the more invested in it they are, the more entrenched their conclusion becomes, and the more obvious it appears that all evidence pointed that way from the very beginning. It is increasingly difficult for police and prosecutors to consider alternative perpetrators or theories of a crime.


====Outcome bias====
====Outcome bias====
Like hindsight bias, “outcome bias” involves projecting subsequent “outcomes” onto observed behaviour, only about the quality of a suspect’s decision. Subjects are more likely to judge as bad a suspect’s decision to operate when they are told the patient died during surgery than when told the patient survived. This is the operator error presumption from {{fieldguide}}
Like hindsight bias, “outcome bias” involves projecting subsequent “outcomes” onto observed behaviour, only about the quality of a suspect’s decision. Subjects are more likely to judge as bad a suspect’s decision to operate when they are told the patient died during surgery than when told the patient survived.  
 
This is the operator error presumption from {{fieldguide}}


====Sunk cost fallacy====
====Sunk cost fallacy====

Revision as of 15:35, 26 July 2024

By tunnel vision, we mean that “compendium of common heuristics and logical fallacies,” to which we are all susceptible, that lead actors in the criminal justice system to “focus on a suspect, select and filter the evidence that will “build a case” for conviction, while ignoring or suppressing evidence that points away from guilt.” This process leads investigators, prosecutors, judges, and defence lawyers alike to focus on a particular conclusion and then filter all evidence in a case through the lens provided by that conclusion.

The Multiple Dimensions of Tunnel Vision in Criminal Cases by Keith Findley and Michael Scott (2006)

Do not attribute to malice what can satisfactorily be explained by stupidity.

Hanlon’s razor

To a man with a hammer, everything looks like a nail.

—Abraham Maslow

Prosecutor’s tunnel vision
/ˈprɒsɪkjuːtəz/ /ˈtʌnᵊl/ /ˈvɪʒᵊn/ (n.)
The collection of biases and cognitive gin-traps that can lead prosecutors — those who “prosecute” a particular theory of the world — to stick with it, however starkly it may vary from available evidence and common sense.

So named because it is often literal prosecutors, of crimes, who suffer from it. This kind of tunnel vision has led to notorious miscarriages of justice where innocent people come to be convicted notwithstanding clear and plausible alternative explanations for their ostensible “crimes”.

The same tunnel vision also motivates ideologies, conspiracies and management philosophy: 360-degree performance appraisals, outsourcing, the war on drugs; the worldwide AML military-industrial complex: are all cases where those “prosecuting” the theory stick with it even though the weight of evidence suggests it does not work and may even be counterproductive.

The “prosecutor’s tunnel” begins with clear but simplistic — misleading — models of a messy world. Humans have a weakness for these: we are pattern-matching, puzzle-solving animals. We are drawn to neatness. We resile from intractability as it indicates weakness: that our frail human intellect has been defeated by the ineffable natural order of things.

An elegant hypothesis

Sometimes the sheer elegance of a prosecutor’s case can crowd out common sense and the basic intuition that this cannot be right.

We have built our legal institutions to be vulnerable to this kind of crowding out. Criminal law proceeds upon data and the weight of evidence but disallows “intuition”. Hence, there is an asymmetry: evidence is better at saying what did happen than what did not. This is especially so where there is no direct evidence that the defendant actually did what she is accused of.

Circumstantial evidence does not directly implicate a defendant but is consistent with the prosecution theory. It accumulates: if there is enough of it, and none points away from the defendant, it can tell us something. But, correlation and causation: evidence that is “consistent with” a prosecution theory does not prove it: that JC owns a bicycle is consistent with his competing in the Tour de France; it does not make him any more likely to do it. Evidence can look more meaningful than it is. This is where intuition ought to be able to help us.

As it is, intuition’s role is relegated to underpinning the presumption of innocence. A prosecutor must prove guilt; the accused need not prove anything: she cannot be expected to explain what happened for the simple reason that and innocent person should have no better idea about it than anyone else. The jury, we hope, leans on its intuition when conjuring doubts.

Experience tells us otherwise. In what follows, JC takes three notorious cases from the antipodes to see what can happen when, with no direct evidence, those arguing the case become afflicted with tunnel vision, and intuition and common sense are relegated behind “data” and circumstantial evidence. Then we will look at what causes this condition.

A ring of dust around Ayers Rock

Lindy and Michael Chamberlain and their three children were camping at Ayers Rock in central Australia in August 1980.[1] They were relaxing with other campers around a campfire when Lindy heard a disturbance near the tent where her infant daughter Azaria was sleeping. As she went to check on the baby she thought she saw a dingo running out of the tent. When she got to the tent, the child was gone.

Lindy raised the alarm at once. Azaria was never found.

Dingo attacks are rare, and the police believed Lindy was behaving strangely. Regarding the “dingo” explanation as absurd, quickly they concluded that Lindy had murdered and disposed of her baby. Their media management was such that before long, the public believed it, too.[2]

The police built their case from the little positive evidence they had: Lindy’s absence from the campfire, her strange religious beliefs (the Chamberlains were Seventh-Day Adventists), her odd behaviour when interviewed and critically what appeared to be spattered infant blood in the footwell of the Chamberlain’s car.

But many aspects of the police case were highly implausible: Lindy was absent for no more than five or ten minutes, so logistically, it would have been hard to murder Azaria in the way proposed — with blunt scissors — dispose of the body and all evidence before returning to the campsite to raise the alarm. Never mind how unlikely it was for a mother — let alone a devout Christian mother — to murder her own infant in cold blood.

Nevertheless, in 1982, Lindy Chamberlain was convicted of Azaria’s murder. She spent three and a half years in prison before Azaria’s matinee jacket was found, four kilometres from the campsite, at the entrance to a dingo lair. Lindy was quickly released and pardoned, but her conviction was not finally quashed until 1992.

The “blood spatter” in the footwell of the Chamberlains’ Holden Torana turned out, much later, to be a standard sound-deadening compound applied during the car’s manufacture.

Satanic panic in the Garden City

In 1991, Peter Ellis, a childcare worker at a daycare centre in New Zealand was charged with horrific abuse of several preschool children in his care.[3] Police alleged, on the children’s own evidence that, among other things, Ellis abducted children en masse during the day, took them across town to a flat where he subjected them to bizarre rituals and acts of unthinkable cruelty and violence before returning them to the creche unobserved before their parents were due to collect them at the end of the day.

In 1993 Ellis was convicted on 16 counts of child sex abuse against seven children.

But none of the allegations was true.

In total, police and social workers interviewed 118 children but presented evidence from just 20. They discarded evidence from children who did not report abuse and those whose claims were patently impossible (some claimed amputation of organs that they still possessed).

Therefore, the evidence put before the court — and fully disclosed to the defence — appeared more credible than it might have had it been viewed in the wider context. Police interview techniques may have encouraged the children to embellish their stories or make them up altogether.

Ellis, who died in 2019, was finally exonerated posthumously in 2022.

Murder in the family

At 6:45 am on the morning of June 20 1994, twenty-two-year-old David Bain returned from his Dunedin paper round to find his whole family had been shot dead.[4] He did not discover this immediately: it was midwinter dark at that hour, in the deep south of New Zealand. Without switching on a light, David first went downstairs to put on a load of laundry. He later told police it was so dark he did not notice his father’s bloodstained clothes on the machine and inadvertently washed them with his own, obliterating key evidence that might have exonerated him.

Returning upstairs, David discovered his father Robin lying in the living room beside a .22 rifle with a bullet in his head. He then found his mother, two sisters and younger brother Stephen all dead in their bedrooms. Stephen appeared to have put up a fight.

There was a note typed on the family computer. It said, “You were the only one who deserved to live.”

David placed an agitated call to emergency services. It was recorded and remains a part of the public record.[5]

David told police his father, motivated by a troubled relationship with the family, must have murdered the family before typing the note on the computer to the absent David and turning the gun on himself.

Notwithstanding David’s account, based on circumstantial evidence including bloodstains on his clothing and spectacles, his fingerprints on the rifle, abrasions on his body consistent with a struggle with Stephen, and the dearth of physical evidence pointing to his father, David was convicted of all five murders.

David maintained his innocence. Joe Karam, a former New Zealand rugby international, led a campaign to challenge David’s conviction. It uncovered procedural shortcomings, inconsistencies and oversights in the police investigation and handling of evidence.

Twenty years after the original trial, the Privy Council quashed Bain’s convictions and ordered a retrial. After the second trial, David Bain was acquitted of all charges. He remains a free man.

Narrative biases

These cases illustrate the problem of relying on circumstantial evidence: with no independent direct evidence, one tends to start with a hypothesis and fit whatever secondary and forensic evidence you have into it, discarding whatever does not fit. This is the classic tunnel vision scenario. It can afflict those who would defend a suspect just as firmly as those who prosecute them.

All kinds of theories circulated owing to the Chamberlains’ unusual religious beliefs and “odd behaviour” in the aftermath of Azaria’s disappearance. But devout Christianity is hardly a solid prior indicating a tendency to murder. Nor is “odd behaviour” in the aftermath of a mother’s most extreme psychological trauma. Who would not behave oddly in those circumstances?

That anyone could bring themselves to cold-bloodedly murder a nine-week-old baby is hard to imagine. Statistically, it is highly improbable. That the child’s own mother would is, in the absence of compelling evidence, preposterous. To even start with this theory you must surely have compelling grounds to believe it over all other possibilities — if not credible eye-witness evidence, then a documented history of violence, behavioural volatility or psychiatric illness grave enough to overthrow the strong human instinct to protect vulnerable infants. Lindy Chamberlain had no such history.

If there is any plausible alternative explanation for the baby’s disappearance, there must have been a reasonable doubt. It need not be more probable than the prosecution case: just not out of the question. Lindy Chamberlain provided one: a dingo snatching the child might have been unprecedented, but it was possible. There were dingoes in the area. They are predators. They are strong enough to carry away a human infant. A dingo was no less likely than a new mother noiselessly murdering her own infant just yards from a group of independent witnesses. That ought to have been the end of it.

Likewise, what Peter Ellis was alleged to have done is extraordinarily improbable. There are few documented cases of ritualistic abuse on that scale anywhere in the world. There are none in New Zealand. For such a thing to have happened without any prior evidence of such behaviour, with no adult witnesses, no one noticing the absent children and for none of the children to bear any trace of their supposed injuries makes it even less likely.

And there was a plausible alternative: nothing happened at all. All that was required for that to be true was for preschool children, perhaps at the prompt of interviewers already in the grip of prosecutor’s tunnel vision, to make things up. By comparison with “untraceable, unwitnessed, wide-scale ritual satanic abuse”, “children exercising their imaginations to please adults” is not improbable.

It is different for David Bain. While it is true that familicide is extremely rare and, therefore, absent prior evidence, highly improbable, there is no question that the Bain family were murdered. The only question was by whom.

On David’s own theory, only two people could have done it: his father and himself. It was, therefore, definitely familicide: the abstract improbability of that explanation is therefore beside the point. The probability that David was responsible is therefore greatly higher: before considering any further evidence there is a 50% chance he was responsible.

And a lot of the further evidence pointed in his direction. To not be the murderer, on his own evidence, David would have been extremely unlucky — forgetting to turn on the light, inadvertently disposing of exculpatory evidence, having incriminating injuries he could not explain — while no such evidence pointed to Robin. David’s defenders had their own tunnel vision, focusing narrowly on the provenance of each piece of incriminating evidence, identifying formal shortcomings in its value as evidence: questioning the manner of its collection, the chain of custody, raising possibilities of innocent explanations without evidence to support that alternative, and disregarding the wider context of the whole case.

Now, David Bain was acquitted of all charges. On the evidence, the jury could not rule out the possibility that Robin Bain was responsible. Not being satisfied beyond reasonable doubt that David was the perpetrator, he was correctly acquitted at law. But it remains likely that David was the perpetrator.[6] As a piece of judicial procedure, the comparison between Bain’s case and those of Ellis and Chamberlain is stark.

Upstanding citizen turns master criminal. Does well.

Prosecutor’s tunnel vision cases often involve previously law-abiding citizens suddenly committing fiendish crimes without leaving direct evidence to implicate themselves beyond an absent alibi.

Now JC is told that committing violent crimes without leaving any incriminating evidence is extremely hard. Especially in a controlled environment like a daycare centre or a hospital. Serial criminals can operate in these environments — Harold Shipman — but they need to be very careful: over time they will hone their techniques and perfect a modus operandi, acquiring a ghoulish sort of metis.

We should not expect the same flawless execution from first-timers. From hitherto “law-abiding citizens” are learning the ropes we should expect to see slip-ups, giveaways, red flags and smoking guns.

Their absence, again, should tell us something. It reduces the prior probability of foul play. If it is plausible that no crime was committed at all, an absence of incriminating evidence should tell us something.

For Lindy Chamberlain there was no such incriminating evidence. Nor for Peter Ellis. But for David Bain there was.

Standards of proof

The prosecution’s standard of proof is, in theory, high. Courts have discarded the time-honoured phrase beyond reasonable doubt and moved to dumb it down: these days, juries are directed to convict only if they are “sure”. This is meant to mean the same thing, but not all are persuaded that is how juries understand it.[7]

There is some reason to think that juries start with an ad hoc presumption that a defendant is likely to be guilty, at least to the balance of probabilities: if the police were competent and acted in good faith, why else would she be in the dock?

Where there is only tendentious data supporting guilt and a total lack of “data” supporting innocence — what evidence could there be that you did not do something that did not happen? — there are grounds for confusion here.

Lindy Chamberlain was convicted of her own daughter’s murder, with a pair of blunt scissors, on the (tendentious) evidence of blood in the footwell of the family car.

The intuition that “a sane mother is most unlikely to brutally murder her own nine-week-old child at all, let alone with an improvised weapon and without warning or provocation” was not before the court. The jury did not hear this. Somehow the jury was persuaded not just that she did murder her child, but that there was no plausible alternative explanation for the child’s disappearance.

The three phases of prosecutor’s tunnel vision

So what is “prosecutor’s tunnel vision”, then and how does it come about? JC draws upon The Multiple Dimensions of Tunnel Vision in Criminal Cases by Keith Findley and Michael Scott in the Wisconsin Law Review (2006) and to a smaller extent Robert Cialdini’s Persuasion. The lessons are two-fold:

We are not as rational as we like to think and
Data is never the whole story.

Tunnel vision may afflict those with any kind of a “conviction” opinion: the behaviours strongly resemble those of people holding passionate religious and political persuasions. Once they take root, they are not easily displaced. If we treat prosecutor’s tunnel vision as a type of “emotional conviction”, we can see better how “prosecutors” can be so energetic in defending a bad mental model.

Tunnel vision has three phases: first, the enabling background conditions that make us vulnerable to tunnel vision; second, the pathways into a given tunnel; third, the cognitive biases that keep us there.

Background conditions

Certain dispositions, biases and miscellaneous psychological tics come together to create the conditions for tunnel vision to swamp an earnestly-held narrative:

The “anchoring” effect

When making decisions we “anchor” our expectations on the first information we get. We then recalibrate not against an abstract measure of value, but by reference to our original anchor. Our anchor disproportionately influences our assessment of subsequent facts.

Overconfidence about adjacent fields

Subject matter experts tend to overestimate their judgment of subtle problems, especially those adjacent to their expertise and the overall significance of matters within their expertise. Overconfident subject matter experts are less likely to consider alternative models, explanations, theories or evidence, let alone contradictory ones.

“To a man with a hammer...”

You don’t enlist in the army hoping never to shoot a gun. The police show up for work to detect crime, and prosecutors to prosecute it. They are primed this way, as are we all: to be useful; for their roles to be important and to make a difference. Our aspiration is to find a crime to prosecute. Those who would deter us from that stance may seem like part of the problem.

We tell ourselves archetypal stories: the dogged cop who sticks at her hunch despite Sarge’s threat to see out her career issuing parking tickets and overcomes the shadowy malign forces to save the day for righteousness and the American way. This is how the lead prosecutor of the Central Park Five saw herself.

We do not tell ourselves stories where we are conspiracy-obsessed geeks who are hounding innocent citizens to the electric chair.

Role pressure

Law enforcement agencies will be under pressure to get results. This may lead to missed opportunities: notoriously, despite repeatedly interviewing him, police overlooked Yorkshire Ripper Peter Sutcliffe, a Yorkshireman, because his accent didn’t match their profile of a man with a Wearside accent, based on a voice recording which turned out to be a hoax.

Getting there

Once you are anchored, equipped with a hammer and have started wandering around the house looking for nails, there should still be scope to falsify your operating theory. But again, psychological biases can override the dispassionate application of cool logic.

Extrapolation

Subject matter experts are prone to extrapolate. We are natural problem-solvers and model builders. We slip easily beyond our brief and intrude into matters where we have little experience. A statistician can give us a compelling account of the Bayesian probabilities, the forensic question of who or what caused the excess toxins is a question of forensics and not something a statistician has a better idea about than anyone else.

Precedent: bad heuristics

The greater the expertise, the more grooved the expectations, the stronger the heuristic, the greater our temptation to take that shortcut and presume that this is “one of those” cases. Where it is, the heuristic is a handy shortcut to the right answer. In the rare case where it is not, it can be dangerous. Heuristics are excellent, time-saving devices but when the model is wrong they can lead to trouble.

Base rate neglect

Lawyers are not natural statisticians. “Base rate neglect” — the “prosecutor’s fallacy” — is the natural tendency to ignore the “base rate” of a phenomenon in the population and instead focus on “individuating” information that pertains to the specific case in front of us. Here Lindy Chamberlain and Peter Ellis can be contrasted with David Bain.

Be careful with statistics about extremely rare events.

Say a certain test gives a correct result 999 times out of 1,000. That is, it only yields one “false positive” result in a thousand tests. It is tempting to assume that a positive result is conclusive. But if the general rate in the population of the condition it is testing for — the “base rate” — is only one case in 100,000 then for every single true positive result, you should still expect 100 false positives.[8]

The same principle holds for criminal offending: if there is, say, a 1/342,000,000 chance that “so many suspicious deaths could have occurred with the same nurse on duty by sheer chance” and one nurse was in fact on duty for all those suspicious deaths, it may seem utterly damning. But this is to ignore the base rate of how many people are there in the world who murder multiple patients?

On a planet with eight billion people, for the odds of our nurse being a serial killer to as high 1/342,000,000 there would need to be twenty-three. There do not appear to be that many hospital serial killers in the last generation.

Yet “one in three-hundred and forty-two million” was the figure that convicted Dutch nurse Lucia de Berk of serial murder. Had this estimate been correct (it turned out to be a wild underestimate) sheer chance was still a likelier explanation.[9]

Confirmation bias

All observation is theory-dependent: scientists must first have a theory before they can gather evidence to test it: otherwise, how do they know what evidence to look for?

Having picked a bad heuristic, we tend to seek out, interpret, and best remember information that confirms it. We may overweight evidence that supports our theory and disregard or minimise anything that contradicts it.

Convinced that Lindy Chamberlain had murdered her infant daughter Azaria, Police searched high and low for blood, eventually finding something resembling infant blood splattered over the footwell of her husband’s car. It turned out to be sound-deadening material containing iron oxide.

Selective information processing

Focusing on certain pieces of evidence while ignoring others. Prosecutors might only present evidence that strengthens their case and neglect exculpatory evidence that could help the defence. Peter Ellis’ prosecutors interviewed one hundred and eighteen children. Many denied all suggestion of abuse. Some gave plainly preposterous accounts of what went on. They were not called to give evidence. Their statements do not appear to have been fully disclosed to the defence.

Groupthink

Thinking or making decisions as a group in a way that discourages creativity or individual responsibility: Prosecutors might conform to the prevailing opinion within their office, stifling dissenting views and critical analysis of the case. See also Dan Davies’ idea of the “accountability sinks” within an organisation. The Post Office Horizon IT scandal is perhaps the archetypal example of groupthink amongst a group of prosecuting lawyers.

Reductionism

Immersing into technical details that, by themselves and shorn of all context, seem to lead to one conclusion — especially one to which you are already anchored — notwithstanding the wider picture making the hypothesis unlikely. Especially in cases with no direct evidence, there is a great risk of this.


Staying there

Once we are in a tunnel, there are cognitive biases that prevent us from finding our way out.

Hindsight bias and the reiteration effect

In hindsight, people tend to think an eventual outcome was inevitable or more likely than they might have before it happened. “What is the chance that that nice woman you met at the campsite just now will, in three hours, brutally murder her own nine-week-old infant?” versus “Given that this woman’s nine-week-old infant has disappeared from the campsite, and the police suspect her of foul play, what is the change that she brutally murdered her own child?”

Through “hindsight bias” we project knowledge of actual outcomes onto our knowledge of the observed behaviour in the past, without realising that the perception of the past has been tainted by the subsequent information.

Once a person becomes a prime suspect hindsight bias suggests that, upon reflection, the suspect was the inevitable and likely suspect from the beginning. Evidence is malleable in light of this “realisation”.

There is also a “reiteration” effect. Our confidence in a theory increases the more we hear it, independent of its validity. The longer that police, prosecutors and witnesses live with the conclusion of guilt, the more invested in it they are, the more entrenched their conclusion becomes, and the more obvious it appears that all evidence pointed that way from the very beginning. It is increasingly difficult for police and prosecutors to consider alternative perpetrators or theories of a crime.

Outcome bias

Like hindsight bias, “outcome bias” involves projecting subsequent “outcomes” onto observed behaviour, only about the quality of a suspect’s decision. Subjects are more likely to judge as bad a suspect’s decision to operate when they are told the patient died during surgery than when told the patient survived.

This is the operator error presumption from Sidney Dekker’s The Field Guide to Human Error Investigations

Sunk cost fallacy

The inclination to continue an endeavour once money, effort, time or credibility has been invested, even when new evidence suggests the defendant might be innocent. (see also commitment when talking about persuasion)

Antidotes

Q: How many psychiatrists does it take to change a light bulb?
A: Just one; but the light bulb really has to want to change.

Some strategies to counteract the effect, but the predominant one is to want to keep an open mind.

Hanlon’s, and Otto’s razor

“Do not attribute to malice things that can just as well be explained by stupidity.”

Hanlon’s razor

Don’t assume malice where stupidity will do; likewise, per Otto’s razor, don’t attribute to virtue something that could equally be attributed to self-interest; or to skill something that could equally be attributed to dumb luck.

  1. A Perfect Storm: The True Story of the Chamberlains is a fabulous accout of the whole affair.
  2. A common schoolyard joke at the time: Q: What is the ring of dust rising around Ayers Rock? A: The dingoes doing a lap of honour.
  3. Alexander Behse and Ali Jones’ Conviction: The Christchurch Civic Creche Case is an outstanding account of the Peter Ellis case.
  4. Black Hands: A Family Mass Murder
  5. https://www.youtube.com/watch?v=m7HsjKDSaKA
  6. Christchurch Journalist Martin Van Beynen’s fantastic podcast Black Hands compellingly makes this case.
  7. New Law Journal: The Trouble With “Sure”
  8. Assume you test 100,000 people. At a 99.9% accuracy rate, you will expect 99,900 correct results, and 100 false ones. But in that sample of 100,000 you would only expect 1 actual case of the condition. So if you are tested and receive a positive result, you have a 1 in 100 chance that it is a true result.
  9. It turned out the statistics were in any case wrong: the probability of her shift patterns coinciding by chance was reassessed as being more like one in twenty-five. De Berk’s acquittal was overturned in 2010.