Finite and Infinite Games: Difference between revisions

From The Jolly Contrarian
Jump to navigation Jump to search
No edit summary
No edit summary
 
(36 intermediate revisions by the same user not shown)
Line 1: Line 1:
{{a|book review|
{{a|book review|
[[File:Infinite finite game.png|450px|frameless|center]]}}{{br|Finite and Infinite Games: A Vision of Life as Play and Possibility}} by {{author|James P. Carse}}<br>
{{image|Infinite finite game|png|An almost infinite finite game, yesterday.}}}}{{c|Futurism}}''If there is one thing to take from this article, please make it this: read {{author|James P. Carse}}’s magnificent {{br|Finite and Infinite Games: A Vision of Life as Play and Possibility}} and go out of your way to '''avoid''' Simon Sinek’s wretched adaptation, {{br|The Infinite Game}}.''
There is so much in this book. Ostensibly, it is an obscure piece of cod philosophy from a religious studies professor in the mid nineteen-eighties. It might well have silted into the geological record as nothing more than that, but it is having a fertile third age: it has been picked up by [[Life coach|life-coach]] to the [[LinkedIn]] generation, {{author|Simon Sinek}}, and when minds as luminous as {{author|Stewart Brand}}’s speak reverently of it, it may have life above the daisies for a little while yet. Hope so.


The central idea is to divide life into two types of games: finite ones, which are zero-sum competitions played with the intention of winning, and infinite ones, played with the intention of continuing to play. This is to use the expression “game” in conflicting senses; a finite game is one in a narrow sense; an infinite game more like Wittgenstein’s concept of a “language game”.


Finite games have fixed rules, fixed boundaries in time and space and an agreed objective usually to beat the other players. Infinite games have no fixed rules, no fixed boundaries, no fixed teams, and players are free to change the rules if that will help play to continue.  
{{quote|“{{infinity quote}}”
:—{{Author|Douglas Adams}}, {{hhgg}}.}}
Carse was a religious studies professor with an aphoristic style, in the habit of saying things like: <blockquote>“… if you are the genius of what you say to me, I am the genius of what I hear you say. What you say originally I can hear only originally. As you surrender the sound on your lips, I surrender the sound in my ear.”</blockquote>As such, [[Finite and Infinite Games: A Vision of Life as Play and Possibility|''Finite and Infinite Games'']] might well have silted into the geological record, somewhere between Erich von Däniken and [[The End of History and the Last Man|Francis Fukuyama]], never to be heard from again until being recycled for peat — but since [[Simon Sinek]]<ref>[[The Infinite Game|''The Infinite Game'']] by [[Simon Sinek]] (2019), though Sinek’s book is a truly terrible misreading of Carse’s point it really bears almost no resemblance to Carse’s original and completely misses the subtle epigrammatic subtext — as such we heartily recommend you steer well clear of it.</ref> recently wrote about it, it is having a fertile third age, and when minds as luminous as [[Stewart Brand]]’s speak reverently of it, there might be life for it yet above the daisies.


It is important, in life, not to confuse the two. The thrust of Sinek’s book is to insist that much of modern life does: that when we carry over [[metaphor]]<nowiki/>s from sport and war — the quintessential finite games — and apply them to business and politics we make a profound error: when we take on infinite players in what we take to be a finite game, we bog ourselves down in intractable quagmires: Vladamir Putin, take note. This observation is appealing, and intuitively right, but there is much more to Carse’s original thesis than that.
I hope so.


Carse, who died last year, is wilfully aphoristic in his literary style, and this is off-putting.<ref>Notably, Carse’s speaking style is much ''less''  cryptic and talks he gavve about the infinite game concept are worth checking out. See for example his talk to the Long Now Foundation: [https://longnow.org/seminars/02005/jan/14/religious-war-in-light-of-the-infinite-game/ Religious Wars in Light of the Infinite Game].</ref> He often says things like:
=== What are “finite” and “infinite” games? ===
{{quote|Of infinite players we can also say that if they play they play freely; if they ''must'' play, they cannot ''play''.}}
Carse’s central idea is that much if life is comprised of two types of “game”: [[Zero-sum game|zero-sum]] competitions that we play to ''win,'' and unbounded collaborative games, that we play to ''continue playing''.


Now this is important, but the book would be better — and more scrutable — had Carse taken more time to explain what he means by this. On the other hand, Carse’s theory is fundamentally [[Relativism|relativist]]; he assigns as much of the credit for successful communication to the listener’s imagination as the speaker’s intention, and freely asserts that the two may be different: 
A '''finite game''' is, in the narrow sense, a ''contest:'' fixed rules, fixed boundaries in time and space, an agreed objective and, usually, a winner and a loser. For example, a football game, boxing match, a [[OODA loop|dog-fight]] or a board game.Notably, both [[Chess]] and [[Go]] are ''finite'' games. Litigation is perhaps the perfect, idealised finite game.


{{Quote|The paradox of genius exposes us directly to the dynamic of open reciprocity, for if you are the genius of what you say to me, I am the genius of what I hear you say. What you say originally I can hear only originally. As you surrender the sound on your lips, I surrender the sound in my ear.}}
An '''infinite game''' has no fixed rules, boundaries, or teams; participants can agree change rules or roles as they see fit, to help play to continue. For example, a market, a community, a business, a team or a scientific [[paradigm]]. Compared with finite contest, infinite games are ([[Quod erat demonstrandum|Q.E.D.]]) nebulous arrangements but one thing is clear: there are no winners and losers. The idea is to ''avoid'' a final result. Everyone plays to keep playing, and keep others playing. A commercial negotiation is the idealised infinite game.


This being the case, Carse may have been intentionally gnomic, wilfully leaving room for listeners to make what they will of his mystic runes. This may not be to everyone’s taste — perhaps why Mr. Sinek has been able to make such hay elucidating it.<ref>{{br|The Infinite Game}} by {{author|Simon Sinek}} (2019) ([https://g.co/kgs/J4Mg35 see here]).</ref> But, irony: the job of imaginatively construing what Mr. Carse meant by his cryptic aphorisms is a kind of infinite game of its own — one that Mr. Sinek is playing pretty well.  
Finite games are from Mars, via [[Thomas Hobbes]] and a team of [[Litigation lawyer|litigators]].


So, let us join in.
Infinite games are from Venus, via [[Adam Smith]] and his team of [[Sales|salespeople]] and [[Structurer|structurers]].


Carse presents the “finite” versus “infinite” dichotomy through the prism of other dualities, which are interesting in themselves:
=== Exclusive and inclusive ===
Their very nebulousness means infinite games are ''inclusive'', and you can play many of them at the same time. We all do, with our careers, families, friendships, communities and social groups. Their boundaries being both fluid and porous, these infinite games permeate, elide, intersect, interlock and amalgamate, and as they do a skilled player adjusts her play.


===Training versus education===
Finite games tend to be ''exclusive'': once you are in one, it dominates whatever else you could otherwise be doing: it is — at least symbolically — a fight to the death, so you can be forgiven for being preoccupied. Since you know where you may go, what you may do, and when it must end, it is possible to sacrifice whatever other interests you may have had while you play the finite game.
{{Quote|“To be prepared against surprise is to be ''trained''. To be prepared for surprise is to be ''educated''.”}}When we play finite games,  we ''train'', but do not need ''education''. A tactician works out moves, devises playbooks, and solves equations, presenting all to the players for ingestion and later regurgitation. All being well, by clinical execution, players overcome their opposition. The team that wins is the one that executes most effectively. Players do not make up a plan as they go: their judgment is limited to selecting which part of the plan to execute when, and in response to what. Preparation is everything. The idea is to eliminate surprise by having, as far as possible, worked them out, and where computing all possible outcomes is not possible, to have computed more possible outcomes than your opponent.  


This is the modernist, computerised model of operation: fast, perfect calculation. One does not want variability. The last thing you want is a player using her initiative: that can ruin everything.
Infinite game being naturally fluid, they can wrap ''around'' a finite game, but not vice versa.


This strategy works where all parameters are fixed and all possible outcomes at least knowable in theory — [[zero-sum game]]<nowiki/>s, [[simple system]]<nowiki/>s, football matches — but does not ''always'' work in the dancing landscapes of [[Complex system|complex adaptive system]]<nowiki/>s. If you prepared for chess, your work will be for naught if the game morphs into draughts — or, just as likely, cookery, music, or electronics. Here, instead of eliminating surprise, you equip yourself to deal with it: you need not answers but tools, [[heuristic]]<nowiki/>s and a facility with [[:Category:Metaphor|metaphor]].
=== Not to be confused ===
In any case, it is important in life to know when you are playing a finite game, and when you are involved in infinite play, and not to confuse them.


===Power versus strength===
The thrust of Simon Sinek’s book is that in much of modern life we ''do'' confuse them: that when we carry over the “finite” [[Metaphor|metaphors]] of sport and war into business and politics, and play infinite games to win them, we make a [[category error]].
{{power versus strength quote}}We speak often about power


===Society versus culture===
But the distinction is subtler than it at first appears. A football ''match'' is finite; a football ''team'' is infinite. The team plays each match to defeat its opponent utterly. But in a broader sense, every football team needs opponents, and not just so it has someone to wallop every Saturday. It is important for the team’s future that it could realistically lose — indeed that, on occasion, it ''does'' lose — so that the games it plays offer the realistic prospect of “drama” (and not merely “theatrics”).
===The theatrical versus the dramatic===
{{Quote|{{indent|Inasmuch as a finite game is intended for conclusion, inasmuch as its roles are scripted and performed for an audience, we shall refer to finite play as ''theatrical''. [...]}}
{{Indent|Inasmuch as infinite players avoid any outcome whatsoever, keeping the future open, making all scripts useless, we shall refer to infinite play as ''dramatic''.}}
{{Indent|Dramatically, one ''chooses to be'' a mother. Theatrically one ''takes on the role'' of mother.<ref>Section 15.</ref>}}}}
This is a harder distinction to glom, especially since  Carse concedes that during a finite game the action is “provisionally” dramatic, since the players write the script as they go along. But the object of the game is to ''kill'' the drama by making the outcome inevitable. So provisional, and hostile, to drama.
===Poeitas===


== Original research ==
While a football team never wishes to lose any ''particular'' match — each is a finite game — in the long run it must lose ''some'' matches in general, lest spectators and players get bored. This is an infinite game. No-one wants to be beaten every time. No-one wants to win every time. No-one wants to watch a foregone conclusion. Ergo, we play finite games ''in the context of a broader infinite game''.
There are many resonances here with some of the JC’s other favourite big ideas.
 
== The finite versus the infinite ==
Carse spends much of ''Finite and Infinite Games'' (unfavourably) comparing finite with infinite play. If much of what we tend to see as an existential struggle need not be anything of the kind, it is worth understanding these structural differences.
 
They have strong resonances with some of the JC’s other favourite big, odd ideas.


===“Historic” versus “prospective”===
===“Historic” versus “prospective”===
Many distinctions between finite and infinite games boil down to their historical perspective: those that look backwards, concerning themselves with what has already been established and laid down — as agreed rules, formal boundaries and limited time periods for resolution necessarily do — will tend to be finite in nature; those that are open-ended, forward looking, and indeterminate concerned with what has yet to happen, and is necessarily unknown, are infinite.
The criteria for a finite game — agreed rules, formal boundaries and a limited period for one side to prevail over the other — means they are “historic” in nature. Even as you play them, you proceed by reference to ''risk'' — calculable probabilities for a known set of possible outcomes — and not ''uncertainty'' — unknown, or unknowable outcomes.<ref>“In a world of risk (“small world”), all alternatives, consequences, and probabilities are known. In uncertain (“large”) worlds, some of this information is unknown or unknowable.” — [https://www.frontiersin.org/articles/10.3389/fnins.2012.00105/full Kirsten Volz and Gerd Gigerenzer]</ref>
 
The result of a football game is only certain at the end, and is a function of ''what happened''. What ''could'' have happened but did not, and what ''might'' happen in the future, if things were only ''different'', is of no concern to anyone playing a finite game.
 
Side-bar for legal eagles: the common law — based as it is on the doctrine of precedent; you know, “what has been decided before” — is dispositionally historic. ''Until it isn’t.'' For what are the great cases, the law reports and textbooks if they are not a catalogue of all the times the courts ''made something new''?
 
By contrast, infinite games, where the object is to find a way to carry on, care little about what has already happened, other to learn from the experience do more of what worked and less of what didn’t. What’s done is done. The challenge is figuring out ''what’s coming next''. This is necessarily prospective. Infinite games harness knowledge and experience to look ''forward''.
 
=== Theatrical and dramatic ===
Carse describes historical, close-ended games as “theatrical,” in the sense that they run on pre-laid rails and can only have results from a range of outcomes that have been determined in advance. This, he contrasts with real “drama”, where by avoiding outcomes, players must improvise to keep the future open. There may be ''some'' drama in a finite game — we may not know ''who'' will win the World Cup — but that drama is only provisional, since it will ultimately be resolved in an expected, probabilistic way:  we do know that one team will win, and 31 will not.
 
Now, historically-focused finite games are fine'','' if that’s what floats your boat: there is no harm and much reward to be had from football, as long as everyone understands the “theatricality” of what’s going on. But to use backward-looking techniques to resolve forward-looking, indeterminate scenarios — to treat the future as a calculable risk rather than an unknowable uncertainty — is to make a [[category error]].
 
This is what business [[Thought leader|thought-leaders]] who use sports [[Metaphor|metaphors]] do.
 
=== The Global Financial Crisis and the lives of the universe ===
[[File:25 sigma event.png|center|thumb|600x600px|Expect a global financial crisis to happen once in several trillion trillion trillion times this long. ''[subs: can we check that?]'']]
<blockquote>“We were seeing things that were 25 [[standard deviation]] moves, several days in a row”.<ref>David Viniar, Chief Financial Officer, [[Goldman|Goldman Sachs]], August 2007.</ref></blockquote>Like the [[common law]], markets are dispositionally historic ''until they aren’t''. Finite techniques work well enough, much of the time, because infinite environments can resemble finite games, much of the time.
 
In “ordinary market conditions”, commerce does seem to operate according to an established order, existing conventions and what is already known. Rules feel fixed. Competition is apparent. Institutions are profitable, market titans are powerful — if not necessarily “strong” — the crowd is wise and everything runs as if impelled by an invisible hand. ''Until it doesn’t''.
 
Why do we prefer finite, historical, backward-looking techniques over forms of infinite play? ''Because they are cheaper to implement and easier to manage''. As long as the environment is predictable, a “historic” approach delivers ''efficiency, consistency'' and ''certainty''. Executives can exercise central control ''as if they were playing a finite game''. They can manage by algorithm. They can use dependable machines, and dispense with unreliable meatware. They can [[Scale|''scale'']], and their risks and returns scale proportionately. This is why they are so fond of sporting metaphors.
 
When the assumption of finitude breaks down — when normal and fat-tailed distributions diverge — [[scale]] becomes a monster. Just ask David Viniar, or [[Black-Scholes option pricing model|Myron Scholes]], or [[Long-Term Capital Management|John Meriwether]], or [[Lehman|Dick Fuld]], or the prime brokers to [[Archegos]].
 
Suddenly, probability metaphors fail. ''One'' twenty-five standard-deviation move is ''preposterous''. You would not expect one in several trillion, trillion lives of the universe, let alone “several days in a row”.<ref>You would expect a “25-sigma move” on one in 1.3 billion billion billion billion billion billion billion billion billion billion billion billion billion billion days, which is several trillion trillion trillion trillion times as long as the life (to date) of the known universe. More on this fascinating topic in our [[normal distribution]] article.</ref>
[[File:Normal vs fat-tailed distribution.png|center|thumb|600x600px|The green bit: normal, but dull. Most events happen here, whether in a finite or infinite game. The orange bit: normal but entertaining. Most non-dull events happen here (if an infinite game); almost all of them (if a finite game). The red bit: terrifying/thrilling. Almost no such events happen in a finite game; a small but significant number will happen in an infinite game.]]
 
Finite games are concerned with risk. Infinite ones are concerned with uncertainty. But risk and uncertainty are hard to tell apart in normal times. For the parts of a [[normal distribution]] that roughly resemble a “fat-tailed” distribution — most of it — historical approaches will work passably well for both, as long as the events fall within the middle, which for the most part they do.
 
===Power and strength ===
{{quote|“A powerful person is one who brings the past to an outcome, settling all its unresolved issues. A strong person is one who carries the past into the future, showing that none of its issues is capable of resolution. Power is concerned with what has already happened; strength with what has yet to happen. Power is finite in amount, strength cannot be measured because it is an opening and not a closing act. Power refers to the freedom persons have ''within'' limits, strength to the freedoms persons have ''with'' limits.}}
 
Power will always be restricted to a relatively small number of selected persons. Anyone can be strong.”</blockquote>It is [[Disdain fashionable things. Especially ideas.|fashionable]] in our time to speak loosely about “power” — much of [[critical theory]] resolves a manifesto against the violence [[Power structure|power structures]] do to the marginalised — and Carse’s distinction between “power” and “strength” is a good reminder to exercise care here.
 
Sure, social organisations can be pernicious, but most are not. Families are power structures. So are local communities. Cricket clubs. Parent-teacher associations. [[Critical theory|Critical theories]] themselves are [[Paradigm|paradigms]] — social hierarchies of just this kind. Any form of communal organisation more developed than flapping around in primordial sludge involves some compromise of interests and some hierarchy.  These don’t ''have'' to be destructive: they can be ''con''structive, enabling, levers to prosperity and betterment for everyone who wants it. If we call such a centralised, curated, defended store of knowledge for sharing a “strength structure” it does not sound so ominous.
 
=== Society and culture: awards versus potential ===
Carse distinguishes between “society” — historical, bounded — and culture” — a provisional alignment of values primed for onward progress. He may have described a [[power structure]] as of “society” and a “strength structure” as of “culture”. The historic, zero-sum nature of finite games contrasts with the prospective, permissive nature of infinite ones.
 
''Society'' is finite, bounded, and patriotic: it functions ''in order to'' establish a hierarchy, bestowing status, titles, honorifics and awards based on what has already happened. These emblems of past victories and achievements grant certain participants [[formal]] status. They are markers of acquired power (and not potential strength). Those with such status are impelled to defend and reinforce the hierarchy because they are have done well in it. One desires the permanence of society because it vouches safe the permanence of one’s titles and prizes.
 
''Culture'' is infinite, unbounded, endlessly creative and sees its history not as destiny, but tradition: a narrative that has been started but is yet to be completed and that may be adjusted as required. That said, culture is a deep layer: it has mass and momentum, and will not change quickly, but it ''does'' change over time.<ref>Stewart Brand’s idea of “[[pace layering]]” is another one of the JC’s favourite big, odd ideas. Stay tuned.</ref>
 
== Top-down versus bottom-up ==
In the same way finite games are backward-looking and not prospective, they imply centralised over distributed decision-making. The ingenuity is in the middle — or, in a hierarchy, at the top and those at the edges are just there to carry out instructions.
 
Thus, football managers formulate strategy and recruit players best able to execute it, drilling them with pre-formulated tactics, plays and set-pieces. Indeed, managers are so important that they are not ''allowed'' to intervene during the match and must delegate that role to an on-field captain who directs operations as the game unfolds. Under these circumstances, a well-coached team of ordinary players may prevail over a disorganised assembly of better athletes. This is the lesson of Michael Lewis’ {{br|Moneyball: The Art of Winning an Unfair Game}}, and the [[falsification]] of the “Galácticos” strategy of buying the best players money can buy, and expecting their virtuosity to prevail.<ref>There are [https://www.theatlantic.com/entertainment/archive/2011/09/the-many-problems-with-moneyball/245769/ those who doubt the Moneyball story], and [[Blockbusters: Why Big Hits and Big Risks are the Future of the Entertainment Business|those who think the Galácticos largely had it right]].</ref>
 
Elite coaching works because rules are fixed, variables known, and there are tight parameters around what players can do, where they can do it.
 
Now as far as business is a ''finite'' game, there is much to take from this. Out in the field, [[form]] dominates [[substance]]: the most vital talents are those who formulate rules, work out [[Algorithm|algorithms]], devise [[Playbook|playbooks]] and source — or ''outsource'' the personnel who will faithfully and efficiently follow the plan.
 
''If'' business is a finite, zero-sum game, there are a few implications:
 
Firstly, ''brilliant minds belong at the top of the organisation'': they do the most inspired thinking. They come up with the best plan. Securing “the person with the best plan” is worth paying ''extraordinary'' amounts of money for.
 
Secondly, the organisation’s sacred quests are the ''creation of excellent process'' and ''optimising the cost of carrying it out''.
 
Thirdly, those whose job is to put the leadership’s plans into practice must, as far as possible, ''follow instructions'' as quickly, flawlessly and cheaply as possible. If your unique selling point is your central strategy, the last thing you want your players to do is ''improvise''. They should act like automatons. In a perfect world, they would ''be'' automatons.
 
Note the drift: for operational staff, it is towards ''efficiency''; for executive administrative staff, it is towards ''excellence''.
 
But if business is an ''infinite'' game, we have a different proposition. The rules aren’t fixed. We can’t predict where the game will go or what other players will do or, for that matter, who’s even playing. There is no common end-goal. A super-coach with a pre-determined strategy is no good. Here you ''do'' want Galácticos — only ones with a talent not for closing out historical conflicts, but seeing new possibilities, creating new metaphors, building new narratives.
 
Carse calls these players “''poietai''” — a Platonic concept meaning something like “poet” — an unfortunate label if you want to go across with sports-obsessed [[Master of Business Administration|MBA]]<nowiki/>s — which we might also render as “''creatives''”.
 
In any case, infinite players are not ''competing'', but ''creating''.
 
We ''want'' creative players to be virtuosos, and not rule-followers. They must have the freedom and resource to carry on — to augment the game. The coach’s role is to build out a simple, robust and permissive infrastructure that lets creatives communicate, puts tools in their hands, enables them to reallocate resources as they see fit. The coach’s overarching goal should be to empower players to make quick and effective decisions  in the field, and otherwise to ''keep out of the way''.
 
This is quite the opposite model to the super-coach: here the greatest value is provided at the edges of the organisation. The bottom-up model: ''laissez-faire''; [[invisible hand]]; evolutionary.
 
=== Form and substance ===
We have argued [[High modernism|elsewhere]], at [[Tedium|tedious]] length, that the great curse of [[Modernism|modernity]] is the primacy of [[Substance and form|form over substance]].
 
In [[Finite game|finite games]] that distinction can be trivial; in an infinite game it is not.
 
In a backward-looking, proven, data-complete universe, ''substance is simply a specific articulation of form''. The universe is solved; there is an exclusive optimal move and it can be derived from first principle. Substance follows from — depends on — form.
 
Form is an axiom; substance is its articulation with numbers. If you have right equation you will get the right answer. This depends on the universe being bounded, all rules determined, all [[Unknowns|knowns known.]] It depends, therefore, on ''the conditions existing for a [[finite game]]''.
 
Where the universe is not bounded, where rules change, where unknowns swamp knowns<ref>[[Signal-to-noise ratio|All data is from the past]]. Seeing as there is an infinite amount of data from the future, the portion of the available data we have is, effectively, nil.</ref> — where the [[Infinite game|game is ''infinite'']] ''substance is not a function of form''. There are no equations, axioms or formulae to follow when interacting with [[Complex system|complex adaptive systems]].
 
== It’s all well in theory ==
 
=== This will all take time, patience and persistence ===
''Finite and Infinite Games'' is a work of abstract principle, not a practical guide to life. Metaphors cannot rid the world of suffering, not resolve the intractable mess that is our world. Our institutions have fashioned themselves over aeons in their own images. They will not change overnight.
 
We should not expect an over-managed multitude of hide-bound rule-followers to pivot overnight to enlightened, terra-forming creatives. If you spent your career learning how to follow rules, being told suddenly those at the coal face must “be agile” and figure it out as they go will present as some kind of terrifying nightmare — it will be beyond the capacity of customer-facing staff, and it will represent an existential threat to (''and'' be beyond the capacity of) those in upper middle management, who for decades have grown to like the idea that business administration is the highest form of being. The system will be motivated ''against'' this shift. It will deftly reorganise itself to resist it.
 
That is to say, our narratives, for better or worse, are a matter of ''culture.'' Culture sits deep in the ontology of a system. It moves slowly. It cannot change overnight.
 
=== A third category: interminable games ===
There is a third type of game that Carse may have overlooked, but which increasingly dominates public discourse, and is a kind of hybrid of the two — or a dark inversion of an infinite game: let’s call them “''interminable'' games”.
 
Interminable games are destructive where infinite ones are creative. Instead of seeking to create new worlds and open up possibilities, each side seeks to shut the other one’s existing world down. They are mainly harmless — just tiresome — because neither side will ever win.
 
Does God exist? Is Socialism good? Is Capitalism bad? Are permissionless [[Blockchain|blockchains]] the future? Will string theory explain life, the universe and everything? Whither [[Critical theory|social justice]]? Is [[Brexit]] a success? These are interminable games.


Let me throw in some original research here: historically-focused games are ''fine'': there is no harm and much reward to be had from a game of football, as long as everyone understands the “theatricality” of what is going on; but to apply finite, backward-looking techniques to the “resolution” of ''infinite'' scenarios — necessarily forward-looking, indeterminate problems (in that you don’t even know that there is a problem, let alone what it is) is where you will get into bother.  
Like finite games, they appear to be contests “to the death”. Yet, like infinite games, they must not be finally resolved. The goal is, always, to ''avoid'' final victory and carry on the fight because ,if you win, you have to pack up your banners, disband your army and ''go home''. Therefore, should outright victory impend, likely victors will scramble to change their own terms of reference until they have something else to fight about.


[[File:Normal vs fat-tailed distribution.png|350px|thumb|right|The ostensible similarity between normal and fat-tailed distributions, yesterday.]]It is deceptive in that finite techniques may work perfectly well much of the time, because even infinite environments largely function by reference to established order, existing rules and what is already known: they look, for the most part, like finite games — it’s just that they don’t have to, and are liable to change without notice. As long as they behave themselves, a finite approach is efficient, effective, centrally controllable and provides consistency and certainty. This is why unimaginative business leaders are so fond of sporting metaphors.
This can work because, the rules of engagement are not fixed, or even agreed: each side is playing to its own rules, with total disregard for the other’s, and will change its premises should it appear to be on the brink of victory or defeat.


This, we think, is just an other way of noting that the middle of a [[normal distribution]] resembles the middle of a “fat-tailed” distribution and the same approaches will work passably well for both, as long as the events fall within the middle, which for the most part they do.
=== No boundaries ===
<blockquote>All models are wrong. But some are useful.


=== As single-round and iterated prisoner’s dilemmas ===
— George E. P. Box</blockquote>Ultimately, the distinction between finite and infinite games eludes. The games we play are not all well-defined. What looks today to be an infinite game of creative possibility can, tomorrow resemble a fight to the death. As with any model of the world, we should use it to frame and illuminate, not to rule. ''Finite and Infinite Games'' is no great falsification of the world as we see it: to treat it that way would be wilfully to misunderstand its essential argument.
A finite game can be part of an infinite game but not vice versa. One could regard a sports franchise an an organisation playing an infinite game through the medium of finite games: here its immediate interests in each distinct match — to comprehensively, theatrically, thrash the opposition — is tempered by its wider interest to keep the infinite game going by creating a compelling sporting contest in which there is the drama that one might not, at any time, win. To carry on that wider, infinite game, one’s opponents must not only survive, but ''flourish'' to the point where they can and will beat you in a finite game, thus supplying theatre if not really drama: an unbeatable team is unsatisfying for winners, losers and spectators alike.


And here we wonder a little about the commutability of infinite games into finite ones: sporting matches are like single round prisoner’s dilemmas: zero-sum in a way that recommends only outright domination.  
Instead, it offers us tools to reimagine ourselves, our struggles, our achievements and the world. The more ways we can redraw ourselves, the better we can play the infinite game.


{{sa}}
{{sa}}
*[[Paradigm failure]]
*[[Paradigm failure]]
*[[Interminable game]]
{{ref}}
{{ref}}
{{c|Big ideas}}
{{c|Big ideas|Systems theory}}

Latest revision as of 10:55, 21 February 2024

The Jolly Contrarian’s book review service™


Infinite finite game.png
An almost infinite finite game, yesterday.
Index: Click to expand:

Comments? Questions? Suggestions? Requests? Insults? We’d love to 📧 hear from you.
Sign up for our newsletter.

If there is one thing to take from this article, please make it this: read James P. Carse’s magnificent Finite and Infinite Games: A Vision of Life as Play and Possibility and go out of your way to avoid Simon Sinek’s wretched adaptation, The Infinite Game.


“It wasn’t infinity in fact. Infinity itself looks flat and uninteresting. Looking up into the night sky is looking into infinity — distance is incomprehensible and therefore meaningless. The chamber into which the aircar emerged was anything but infinite, it was just very very very big, so big that it gave the impression of infinity far better than infinity itself.”

Douglas Adams, The Hitch-Hiker’s Guide to the Galaxy.

Carse was a religious studies professor with an aphoristic style, in the habit of saying things like:

“… if you are the genius of what you say to me, I am the genius of what I hear you say. What you say originally I can hear only originally. As you surrender the sound on your lips, I surrender the sound in my ear.”

As such, Finite and Infinite Games might well have silted into the geological record, somewhere between Erich von Däniken and Francis Fukuyama, never to be heard from again until being recycled for peat — but since Simon Sinek[1] recently wrote about it, it is having a fertile third age, and when minds as luminous as Stewart Brand’s speak reverently of it, there might be life for it yet above the daisies.

I hope so.

What are “finite” and “infinite” games?

Carse’s central idea is that much if life is comprised of two types of “game”: zero-sum competitions that we play to win, and unbounded collaborative games, that we play to continue playing.

A finite game is, in the narrow sense, a contest: fixed rules, fixed boundaries in time and space, an agreed objective and, usually, a winner and a loser. For example, a football game, boxing match, a dog-fight or a board game.Notably, both Chess and Go are finite games. Litigation is perhaps the perfect, idealised finite game.

An infinite game has no fixed rules, boundaries, or teams; participants can agree change rules or roles as they see fit, to help play to continue. For example, a market, a community, a business, a team or a scientific paradigm. Compared with finite contest, infinite games are (Q.E.D.) nebulous arrangements but one thing is clear: there are no winners and losers. The idea is to avoid a final result. Everyone plays to keep playing, and keep others playing. A commercial negotiation is the idealised infinite game.

Finite games are from Mars, via Thomas Hobbes and a team of litigators.

Infinite games are from Venus, via Adam Smith and his team of salespeople and structurers.

Exclusive and inclusive

Their very nebulousness means infinite games are inclusive, and you can play many of them at the same time. We all do, with our careers, families, friendships, communities and social groups. Their boundaries being both fluid and porous, these infinite games permeate, elide, intersect, interlock and amalgamate, and as they do a skilled player adjusts her play.

Finite games tend to be exclusive: once you are in one, it dominates whatever else you could otherwise be doing: it is — at least symbolically — a fight to the death, so you can be forgiven for being preoccupied. Since you know where you may go, what you may do, and when it must end, it is possible to sacrifice whatever other interests you may have had while you play the finite game.

Infinite game being naturally fluid, they can wrap around a finite game, but not vice versa.

Not to be confused

In any case, it is important in life to know when you are playing a finite game, and when you are involved in infinite play, and not to confuse them.

The thrust of Simon Sinek’s book is that in much of modern life we do confuse them: that when we carry over the “finite” metaphors of sport and war into business and politics, and play infinite games to win them, we make a category error.

But the distinction is subtler than it at first appears. A football match is finite; a football team is infinite. The team plays each match to defeat its opponent utterly. But in a broader sense, every football team needs opponents, and not just so it has someone to wallop every Saturday. It is important for the team’s future that it could realistically lose — indeed that, on occasion, it does lose — so that the games it plays offer the realistic prospect of “drama” (and not merely “theatrics”).

While a football team never wishes to lose any particular match — each is a finite game — in the long run it must lose some matches in general, lest spectators and players get bored. This is an infinite game. No-one wants to be beaten every time. No-one wants to win every time. No-one wants to watch a foregone conclusion. Ergo, we play finite games in the context of a broader infinite game.

The finite versus the infinite

Carse spends much of Finite and Infinite Games (unfavourably) comparing finite with infinite play. If much of what we tend to see as an existential struggle need not be anything of the kind, it is worth understanding these structural differences.

They have strong resonances with some of the JC’s other favourite big, odd ideas.

“Historic” versus “prospective”

The criteria for a finite game — agreed rules, formal boundaries and a limited period for one side to prevail over the other — means they are “historic” in nature. Even as you play them, you proceed by reference to risk — calculable probabilities for a known set of possible outcomes — and not uncertainty — unknown, or unknowable outcomes.[2]

The result of a football game is only certain at the end, and is a function of what happened. What could have happened but did not, and what might happen in the future, if things were only different, is of no concern to anyone playing a finite game.

Side-bar for legal eagles: the common law — based as it is on the doctrine of precedent; you know, “what has been decided before” — is dispositionally historic. Until it isn’t. For what are the great cases, the law reports and textbooks if they are not a catalogue of all the times the courts made something new?

By contrast, infinite games, where the object is to find a way to carry on, care little about what has already happened, other to learn from the experience do more of what worked and less of what didn’t. What’s done is done. The challenge is figuring out what’s coming next. This is necessarily prospective. Infinite games harness knowledge and experience to look forward.

Theatrical and dramatic

Carse describes historical, close-ended games as “theatrical,” in the sense that they run on pre-laid rails and can only have results from a range of outcomes that have been determined in advance. This, he contrasts with real “drama”, where by avoiding outcomes, players must improvise to keep the future open. There may be some drama in a finite game — we may not know who will win the World Cup — but that drama is only provisional, since it will ultimately be resolved in an expected, probabilistic way: we do know that one team will win, and 31 will not.

Now, historically-focused finite games are fine, if that’s what floats your boat: there is no harm and much reward to be had from football, as long as everyone understands the “theatricality” of what’s going on. But to use backward-looking techniques to resolve forward-looking, indeterminate scenarios — to treat the future as a calculable risk rather than an unknowable uncertainty — is to make a category error.

This is what business thought-leaders who use sports metaphors do.

The Global Financial Crisis and the lives of the universe

Expect a global financial crisis to happen once in several trillion trillion trillion times this long. [subs: can we check that?]

“We were seeing things that were 25 standard deviation moves, several days in a row”.[3]

Like the common law, markets are dispositionally historic until they aren’t. Finite techniques work well enough, much of the time, because infinite environments can resemble finite games, much of the time.

In “ordinary market conditions”, commerce does seem to operate according to an established order, existing conventions and what is already known. Rules feel fixed. Competition is apparent. Institutions are profitable, market titans are powerful — if not necessarily “strong” — the crowd is wise and everything runs as if impelled by an invisible hand. Until it doesn’t.

Why do we prefer finite, historical, backward-looking techniques over forms of infinite play? Because they are cheaper to implement and easier to manage. As long as the environment is predictable, a “historic” approach delivers efficiency, consistency and certainty. Executives can exercise central control as if they were playing a finite game. They can manage by algorithm. They can use dependable machines, and dispense with unreliable meatware. They can scale, and their risks and returns scale proportionately. This is why they are so fond of sporting metaphors.

When the assumption of finitude breaks down — when normal and fat-tailed distributions diverge — scale becomes a monster. Just ask David Viniar, or Myron Scholes, or John Meriwether, or Dick Fuld, or the prime brokers to Archegos.

Suddenly, probability metaphors fail. One twenty-five standard-deviation move is preposterous. You would not expect one in several trillion, trillion lives of the universe, let alone “several days in a row”.[4]

The green bit: normal, but dull. Most events happen here, whether in a finite or infinite game. The orange bit: normal but entertaining. Most non-dull events happen here (if an infinite game); almost all of them (if a finite game). The red bit: terrifying/thrilling. Almost no such events happen in a finite game; a small but significant number will happen in an infinite game.

Finite games are concerned with risk. Infinite ones are concerned with uncertainty. But risk and uncertainty are hard to tell apart in normal times. For the parts of a normal distribution that roughly resemble a “fat-tailed” distribution — most of it — historical approaches will work passably well for both, as long as the events fall within the middle, which for the most part they do.

Power and strength

“A powerful person is one who brings the past to an outcome, settling all its unresolved issues. A strong person is one who carries the past into the future, showing that none of its issues is capable of resolution. Power is concerned with what has already happened; strength with what has yet to happen. Power is finite in amount, strength cannot be measured because it is an opening and not a closing act. Power refers to the freedom persons have within limits, strength to the freedoms persons have with limits.

Power will always be restricted to a relatively small number of selected persons. Anyone can be strong.”It is fashionable in our time to speak loosely about “power” — much of critical theory resolves a manifesto against the violence power structures do to the marginalised — and Carse’s distinction between “power” and “strength” is a good reminder to exercise care here.

Sure, social organisations can be pernicious, but most are not. Families are power structures. So are local communities. Cricket clubs. Parent-teacher associations. Critical theories themselves are paradigms — social hierarchies of just this kind. Any form of communal organisation more developed than flapping around in primordial sludge involves some compromise of interests and some hierarchy. These don’t have to be destructive: they can be constructive, enabling, levers to prosperity and betterment for everyone who wants it. If we call such a centralised, curated, defended store of knowledge for sharing a “strength structure” it does not sound so ominous.

Society and culture: awards versus potential

Carse distinguishes between “society” — historical, bounded — and culture” — a provisional alignment of values primed for onward progress. He may have described a power structure as of “society” and a “strength structure” as of “culture”. The historic, zero-sum nature of finite games contrasts with the prospective, permissive nature of infinite ones.

Society is finite, bounded, and patriotic: it functions in order to establish a hierarchy, bestowing status, titles, honorifics and awards based on what has already happened. These emblems of past victories and achievements grant certain participants formal status. They are markers of acquired power (and not potential strength). Those with such status are impelled to defend and reinforce the hierarchy because they are have done well in it. One desires the permanence of society because it vouches safe the permanence of one’s titles and prizes.

Culture is infinite, unbounded, endlessly creative and sees its history not as destiny, but tradition: a narrative that has been started but is yet to be completed and that may be adjusted as required. That said, culture is a deep layer: it has mass and momentum, and will not change quickly, but it does change over time.[5]

Top-down versus bottom-up

In the same way finite games are backward-looking and not prospective, they imply centralised over distributed decision-making. The ingenuity is in the middle — or, in a hierarchy, at the top — and those at the edges are just there to carry out instructions.

Thus, football managers formulate strategy and recruit players best able to execute it, drilling them with pre-formulated tactics, plays and set-pieces. Indeed, managers are so important that they are not allowed to intervene during the match and must delegate that role to an on-field captain who directs operations as the game unfolds. Under these circumstances, a well-coached team of ordinary players may prevail over a disorganised assembly of better athletes. This is the lesson of Michael Lewis’ Moneyball: The Art of Winning an Unfair Game, and the falsification of the “Galácticos” strategy of buying the best players money can buy, and expecting their virtuosity to prevail.[6]

Elite coaching works because rules are fixed, variables known, and there are tight parameters around what players can do, where they can do it.

Now as far as business is a finite game, there is much to take from this. Out in the field, form dominates substance: the most vital talents are those who formulate rules, work out algorithms, devise playbooks and source — or outsource — the personnel who will faithfully and efficiently follow the plan.

If business is a finite, zero-sum game, there are a few implications:

Firstly, brilliant minds belong at the top of the organisation: they do the most inspired thinking. They come up with the best plan. Securing “the person with the best plan” is worth paying extraordinary amounts of money for.

Secondly, the organisation’s sacred quests are the creation of excellent process and optimising the cost of carrying it out.

Thirdly, those whose job is to put the leadership’s plans into practice must, as far as possible, follow instructions as quickly, flawlessly and cheaply as possible. If your unique selling point is your central strategy, the last thing you want your players to do is improvise. They should act like automatons. In a perfect world, they would be automatons.

Note the drift: for operational staff, it is towards efficiency; for executive administrative staff, it is towards excellence.

But if business is an infinite game, we have a different proposition. The rules aren’t fixed. We can’t predict where the game will go or what other players will do or, for that matter, who’s even playing. There is no common end-goal. A super-coach with a pre-determined strategy is no good. Here you do want Galácticos — only ones with a talent not for closing out historical conflicts, but seeing new possibilities, creating new metaphors, building new narratives.

Carse calls these players “poietai” — a Platonic concept meaning something like “poet” — an unfortunate label if you want to go across with sports-obsessed MBAs — which we might also render as “creatives”.

In any case, infinite players are not competing, but creating.

We want creative players to be virtuosos, and not rule-followers. They must have the freedom and resource to carry on — to augment the game. The coach’s role is to build out a simple, robust and permissive infrastructure that lets creatives communicate, puts tools in their hands, enables them to reallocate resources as they see fit. The coach’s overarching goal should be to empower players to make quick and effective decisions in the field, and otherwise to keep out of the way.

This is quite the opposite model to the super-coach: here the greatest value is provided at the edges of the organisation. The bottom-up model: laissez-faire; invisible hand; evolutionary.

Form and substance

We have argued elsewhere, at tedious length, that the great curse of modernity is the primacy of form over substance.

In finite games that distinction can be trivial; in an infinite game it is not.

In a backward-looking, proven, data-complete universe, substance is simply a specific articulation of form. The universe is solved; there is an exclusive optimal move and it can be derived from first principle. Substance follows from — depends on — form.

Form is an axiom; substance is its articulation with numbers. If you have right equation you will get the right answer. This depends on the universe being bounded, all rules determined, all knowns known. It depends, therefore, on the conditions existing for a finite game.

Where the universe is not bounded, where rules change, where unknowns swamp knowns[7] — where the game is infinitesubstance is not a function of form. There are no equations, axioms or formulae to follow when interacting with complex adaptive systems.

It’s all well in theory

This will all take time, patience and persistence

Finite and Infinite Games is a work of abstract principle, not a practical guide to life. Metaphors cannot rid the world of suffering, not resolve the intractable mess that is our world. Our institutions have fashioned themselves over aeons in their own images. They will not change overnight.

We should not expect an over-managed multitude of hide-bound rule-followers to pivot overnight to enlightened, terra-forming creatives. If you spent your career learning how to follow rules, being told suddenly those at the coal face must “be agile” and figure it out as they go will present as some kind of terrifying nightmare — it will be beyond the capacity of customer-facing staff, and it will represent an existential threat to (and be beyond the capacity of) those in upper middle management, who for decades have grown to like the idea that business administration is the highest form of being. The system will be motivated against this shift. It will deftly reorganise itself to resist it.

That is to say, our narratives, for better or worse, are a matter of culture. Culture sits deep in the ontology of a system. It moves slowly. It cannot change overnight.

A third category: interminable games

There is a third type of game that Carse may have overlooked, but which increasingly dominates public discourse, and is a kind of hybrid of the two — or a dark inversion of an infinite game: let’s call them “interminable games”.

Interminable games are destructive where infinite ones are creative. Instead of seeking to create new worlds and open up possibilities, each side seeks to shut the other one’s existing world down. They are mainly harmless — just tiresome — because neither side will ever win.

Does God exist? Is Socialism good? Is Capitalism bad? Are permissionless blockchains the future? Will string theory explain life, the universe and everything? Whither social justice? Is Brexit a success? These are interminable games.

Like finite games, they appear to be contests “to the death”. Yet, like infinite games, they must not be finally resolved. The goal is, always, to avoid final victory and carry on the fight because ,if you win, you have to pack up your banners, disband your army and go home. Therefore, should outright victory impend, likely victors will scramble to change their own terms of reference until they have something else to fight about.

This can work because, the rules of engagement are not fixed, or even agreed: each side is playing to its own rules, with total disregard for the other’s, and will change its premises should it appear to be on the brink of victory or defeat.

No boundaries

All models are wrong. But some are useful. — George E. P. Box

Ultimately, the distinction between finite and infinite games eludes. The games we play are not all well-defined. What looks today to be an infinite game of creative possibility can, tomorrow resemble a fight to the death. As with any model of the world, we should use it to frame and illuminate, not to rule. Finite and Infinite Games is no great falsification of the world as we see it: to treat it that way would be wilfully to misunderstand its essential argument.

Instead, it offers us tools to reimagine ourselves, our struggles, our achievements and the world. The more ways we can redraw ourselves, the better we can play the infinite game.

See also

References

  1. The Infinite Game by Simon Sinek (2019), though Sinek’s book is a truly terrible misreading of Carse’s point — it really bears almost no resemblance to Carse’s original and completely misses the subtle epigrammatic subtext — as such we heartily recommend you steer well clear of it.
  2. “In a world of risk (“small world”), all alternatives, consequences, and probabilities are known. In uncertain (“large”) worlds, some of this information is unknown or unknowable.” — Kirsten Volz and Gerd Gigerenzer
  3. David Viniar, Chief Financial Officer, Goldman Sachs, August 2007.
  4. You would expect a “25-sigma move” on one in 1.3 billion billion billion billion billion billion billion billion billion billion billion billion billion billion days, which is several trillion trillion trillion trillion times as long as the life (to date) of the known universe. More on this fascinating topic in our normal distribution article.
  5. Stewart Brand’s idea of “pace layering” is another one of the JC’s favourite big, odd ideas. Stay tuned.
  6. There are those who doubt the Moneyball story, and those who think the Galácticos largely had it right.
  7. All data is from the past. Seeing as there is an infinite amount of data from the future, the portion of the available data we have is, effectively, nil.