Finite and Infinite Games: Difference between revisions
Amwelladmin (talk | contribs) No edit summary Tags: Mobile edit Mobile web edit |
Amwelladmin (talk | contribs) No edit summary |
||
Line 4: | Line 4: | ||
{{quote|“{{infinity quote}}” | {{quote|“{{infinity quote}}” | ||
:—{{Author|Douglas Adams}}, {{hhgg}}.}} | :—{{Author|Douglas Adams}}, {{hhgg}}.}} | ||
Ostensibly, {{Br|Finite and Infinite Games}} is a | Ostensibly, {{Br|Finite and Infinite Games}} is a 40-year-old tract of cod philosophy from an obscure religious studies professor. It might well have silted into the geological record — somewhere between Erich von Däniken and [[The End of History and the Last Man|Francis Fukuyama]] — i.e., destined never to be heard from again until it is recycled for peat but having been picked up by [[Life coach|life-coach]] to the [[LinkedIn]] generation, {{author|Simon Sinek}}<ref>{{br|The Infinite Game}} by {{author|Simon Sinek}} (2019) ([https://g.co/kgs/J4Mg35 see here]).</ref> it is having a fertile third age, and when minds as luminous as {{author|Stewart Brand}}’s speak reverently of it, it seems there is life above the daisies for a little while yet. Hope so. | ||
The central idea is this: there are two types of “games” in the world: “finite” ones — [[Zero-sum game|zero-sum]] competitions played with the intention of ''winning'' — and “infinite” ones, played with the intention of ''continuing the play''. Finite games are from Mars, via [[Thomas Hobbes]]; infinite ones from Venus, via [[Adam Smith]].<ref>I am told, incidentally, that it will not to to be “guided by white men who died in the 17th and 18th centuries.” I don’t think it will do to be guided by people who say such inane things.</ref> | |||
In any case to draw this distinction is to use the word “game” in conflicting senses. | |||
A finite game is | A finite game is, in the narrow sense, a ''contest:'' fixed rules, fixed boundaries in time and space, an agreed objective and, usually, a winner and a loser. For example, a football game, boxing match, a [[OODA loop|dog-fight]] or a board game: notably both [[chess]] and [[go]] are finite games. | ||
An infinite game is | An infinite game is more like a “language game”: no fixed rules, boundaries, or teams; participants can agree change rules or roles as they see fit to help play to continue. For example, a market, a community, a business, a team or a scientific [[paradigm]]. These are ([[Quod erat demonstrandum|Q.E.D.]]) nebulous arrangements, of course, but one thing they are definitely ''not'' is contests. There are no winners and losers in an infinite game, since the idea is to avoid a final result. | ||
You may play multiple, interlocking, nested finite games at any time, and you can even embed finite games into infinite ones — though, for obvious reasons, not vice versa — so it is important in life not to ''confuse'' one’s finite and one’s infinite games. The thrust of Sinek’s book is that much of modern life ''does'' confuse them: that when we carry over the [[metaphor]]s of sport and war into business and politics we are tempted to play infinite games to win — that is, as if they were finite games. This is a [[category error]]. We may find ourselves excluded from the game while others carry on. We may find our finite objectives hard to pin down, let alone achieve. | |||
That said, the distinction between the two is less tractable than it at first appears. A football ''match'' is finite; a football ''team | That said, the distinction between the two is less tractable than it at first appears. A football ''match'' is finite; a football ''team'' is infinite. A team plays each match to defeat its opponent utterly; in the wider league, it needs its opponents to survive and flourish, so it can continue to play against them, and so that there is the realistic prospect of drama (and not merely theatrics) on the field. While a team never wishes to lose any ''particular'' match, in the long run it must lose ''some'' matches in general, lest there be no drama: spectators and players get bored. No-one wants to be beaten every time. No-one wants to win every time. No-one wants to watch a foregone conclusion. We play finite games ''in the context of a broader infinite game''. | ||
Carse, who died last year, | Carse, who died last year, was wilfully aphoristic in his literary style. This is off-putting.<ref>Notably, Carse’s speaking style is much ''less'' cryptic and talks he gave about the infinite game concept are worth checking out. See for example his talk to the Long Now Foundation: [https://longnow.org/seminars/02005/jan/14/religious-war-in-light-of-the-infinite-game/ Religious Wars in Light of the Infinite Game].</ref> He would often write things like:{{Quote|The paradox of genius exposes us directly to the dynamic of open reciprocity, for if you are the genius of what you say to me, I am the genius of what I hear you say. What you say originally I can hear only originally. As you surrender the sound on your lips, I surrender the sound in my ear.}}Now this is important, but it would have been better — or, at least, more fathomable — had he explained better what he means by this. That said, this passage assigns as much credit for successful communication to the listener as to the speaker, so perhaps this is the very point. Maybe Carse meant to leave room for listeners to make what they will of his mystic runes. In any case, making head or tail of Carse’s cryptic aphorisms is a kind of infinite game of its own — one that Mr. Sinek is playing pretty well. So, let us join in. | ||
Carse invites us to reframe activities we might see as existential struggles instead as opportunities to build a different future: all it requires is players who are skilled at the infinite game. To do this he sets up a number of dualities: | |||
Carse | |||
===“Training” versus “education”=== | ===“Training” versus “education”=== | ||
Line 58: | Line 56: | ||
Society is ambivalent towards the dreamers and malcontents who imagine a different order — they once broke Mick Jagger on a wheel; now he’s a peer of the realm — but they operate not by directly confronting the established order, but by sketching out an imagined alternative which eventually takes root. | Society is ambivalent towards the dreamers and malcontents who imagine a different order — they once broke Mick Jagger on a wheel; now he’s a peer of the realm — but they operate not by directly confronting the established order, but by sketching out an imagined alternative which eventually takes root. | ||
== Original research == | ==Original research== | ||
There are many resonances here with some of the JC’s other favourite big ideas. | There are many resonances here with some of the JC’s other favourite big ideas. | ||
Line 78: | Line 76: | ||
This, we think, is just an other way of noting that the middle of a [[normal distribution]] resembles the middle of a “fat-tailed” distribution and the same approaches will work passably well for both, as long as the events fall within the middle, which for the most part they do. | This, we think, is just an other way of noting that the middle of a [[normal distribution]] resembles the middle of a “fat-tailed” distribution and the same approaches will work passably well for both, as long as the events fall within the middle, which for the most part they do. | ||
=== “Formal” versus “substantive” === | ===“Formal” versus “substantive”=== | ||
We have argued elsewhere that the great curse of [[Modernism|modernity]] is the primacy of [[Substance and form|form over substance]]. In [[Finite game|finite games]] the distinction between the two can be trivial; in an infinite game it is not. | We have argued elsewhere that the great curse of [[Modernism|modernity]] is the primacy of [[Substance and form|form over substance]]. In [[Finite game|finite games]] the distinction between the two can be trivial; in an infinite game it is not. | ||
Line 85: | Line 83: | ||
Where the universe is not bounded, where rules are unknown or changeable, where unknowns swamp knowns<ref>[[Signal-to-noise ratio|All data is from the past]]. Seeing as there is an infinite amount of data from the future, the portion of the available data we have is, effectively, nil. </ref> — where the [[Infinite game|game is ''infinite'']] — ''substance is not a function of form''. There are no equations, axioms or formulae to follow when interacting with [[Complex system|complex adaptive system]]s. It will be tempting to rely on formulae that tend to work most of the time — the [[Black-Scholes option pricing model|Black Scholes option pricing model]] works most of the time, at least [[Long-Term Capital Management|until it does not]] — but this is a lazy and, at the limit, dangerous, economy. We need a different approach. Instead of the trained — those best equipped to carry out complicated instructions — we need the ''educated'': those best equipped to [[OODA loop|observe, orient, decide and act]]. These people are necessarily skilled, experienced and therefore ''expensive''. | Where the universe is not bounded, where rules are unknown or changeable, where unknowns swamp knowns<ref>[[Signal-to-noise ratio|All data is from the past]]. Seeing as there is an infinite amount of data from the future, the portion of the available data we have is, effectively, nil. </ref> — where the [[Infinite game|game is ''infinite'']] — ''substance is not a function of form''. There are no equations, axioms or formulae to follow when interacting with [[Complex system|complex adaptive system]]s. It will be tempting to rely on formulae that tend to work most of the time — the [[Black-Scholes option pricing model|Black Scholes option pricing model]] works most of the time, at least [[Long-Term Capital Management|until it does not]] — but this is a lazy and, at the limit, dangerous, economy. We need a different approach. Instead of the trained — those best equipped to carry out complicated instructions — we need the ''educated'': those best equipped to [[OODA loop|observe, orient, decide and act]]. These people are necessarily skilled, experienced and therefore ''expensive''. | ||
=== Top-down versus bottom-up === | === Top-down versus bottom-up=== | ||
{{Quote| | {{Quote| | ||
You know, man, when I was a young man in high school<br> | You know, man, when I was a young man in high school<br> | ||
Line 94: | Line 92: | ||
:Lou Reed, ''Coney Island Baby''}} | :Lou Reed, ''Coney Island Baby''}} | ||
Finite games | ==== Finite games as execution of the master plan ==== | ||
Finite games favour top-down game management, with central homunculus instilling in players a defined set of pre-formulated tactics: a coach to formulate them and a captain to see they are executed. Infinite games are bottom up: every player must continually assess her environment and work out what to do based on the information she currently has. Here a “coach” is little more than a central coordinator supplying information and resources to help the players make their own tactical decisions as the need arises. | |||
In a predefined contest, [[form]] dominates substance: we should concentrate our resources at the centre, formulate rules, work out [[algorithm]]s and devise [[Playbook|playbooks]], since if we get this right, success is a matter of execution, and “failure” comes from shortcomings in execution of the plan. | |||
This has a few implications: firstly, it means the brilliant minds belong at the top of the organisation: they do the most inspired thinking. | |||
Secondly, it means there is no more sacred quest than ''the creation of excellent process''. Our most talented personnel are those who can write and maintain formal rules. | |||
Thirdly, it means those at the edges of the organisation whose job is not to formulate policy but to follow it — those who must put the leadership’s plans and algorithms into practice — ''must not think'': they must, so far as possible, just ''follow instructions'': quickly, flawlessly, cheaply. ''They should act like automatons''. If you are in a finite game environment, the ''last'' thing you want your players to do is improvise, or make things up as they go along: that will upset the carefully formulated plan. Players must not just act like machines: ideally, players would ''be'' machines: cheap, reliable and fungible. | |||
Those with an interest in modern corporate management philosophy might recognise this disposition. It is the one that recommends that those who carry out the firm’s day-to-day business and interact with its clients should be [[Downgrading|juniorised]], if they cannot be [[Outsourcing|outsourced]], if they cannot be [[Automation eliminates value but not risk|automated]] — those who formulate strategy and policy and who watch from the Gods should be feted, lionised, and rewarded. | |||
==== Infinite games as virtuoso improvisation ==== | |||
[[Infinite game]]s favour virtuoso performances in the field: in a [[wicked environment]] cheap, quick, accurate machines are no use, and the infrastructure they need to ensure they continue working may get in the way. Rather than being elaborate, internal infrastructure should be simple, robust and permissive — enabling communication, facilitating dynamic reallocation of resources, but fundamentally organising the architecture to empower quick and effective decision-making in the field. Seeing as the idea is not to win but to continue, conferring discretion upon those at the edge of the organisation who must engage with the complex adaptive system outside is not necessarily catastrophic as long as the individuals are experienced experts: they must ''not'' act like machines, and empowered — ''trusted'' to deal with unfolding situations as they perceive them. The ongoing prosperity of the organisation is an [[emergent]] property of the behaviour of these subject matter experts. This is quite the opposite model: here the greatest value is provided at the edges of the organisation. The bottom-up model: ''laissez-faire''; [[invisible hand]]; evolutionary. | [[Infinite game]]s favour virtuoso performances in the field: in a [[wicked environment]] cheap, quick, accurate machines are no use, and the infrastructure they need to ensure they continue working may get in the way. Rather than being elaborate, internal infrastructure should be simple, robust and permissive — enabling communication, facilitating dynamic reallocation of resources, but fundamentally organising the architecture to empower quick and effective decision-making in the field. Seeing as the idea is not to win but to continue, conferring discretion upon those at the edge of the organisation who must engage with the complex adaptive system outside is not necessarily catastrophic as long as the individuals are experienced experts: they must ''not'' act like machines, and empowered — ''trusted'' to deal with unfolding situations as they perceive them. The ongoing prosperity of the organisation is an [[emergent]] property of the behaviour of these subject matter experts. This is quite the opposite model: here the greatest value is provided at the edges of the organisation. The bottom-up model: ''laissez-faire''; [[invisible hand]]; evolutionary. | ||
=== As [[Single-round prisoner’s dilemma|single-round]] and [[Iterated prisoner’s dilemma|iterated prisoner’s dilemmas]] === | ===As [[Single-round prisoner’s dilemma|single-round]] and [[Iterated prisoner’s dilemma|iterated prisoner’s dilemmas]]=== | ||
A finite game can be part of an infinite game but not vice versa. One could regard a sports franchise an an organisation playing an infinite game through the medium of finite games: here its immediate interests in each distinct match — to comprehensively, theatrically, thrash the opposition — is tempered by its wider interest to keep the infinite game going by creating a compelling sporting contest in which there is the drama that one might not, at any time, win. To carry on that wider, infinite game, one’s opponents must not only survive, but ''flourish'' to the point where they can and will beat you in a finite game, thus supplying theatre if not really drama: an unbeatable team is unsatisfying for winners, losers and spectators alike. | A finite game can be part of an infinite game but not vice versa. One could regard a sports franchise an an organisation playing an infinite game through the medium of finite games: here its immediate interests in each distinct match — to comprehensively, theatrically, thrash the opposition — is tempered by its wider interest to keep the infinite game going by creating a compelling sporting contest in which there is the drama that one might not, at any time, win. To carry on that wider, infinite game, one’s opponents must not only survive, but ''flourish'' to the point where they can and will beat you in a finite game, thus supplying theatre if not really drama: an unbeatable team is unsatisfying for winners, losers and spectators alike. | ||
Line 106: | Line 114: | ||
===Problem cases=== | ===Problem cases=== | ||
====The Christians, atheists and their [[interminable game]]s==== | ====The Christians, atheists and their [[interminable game]]s==== | ||
A particular type of argumentative youth — it may not shock you to find that the JC was one, once — will take delight in forming abstract and highly artificial positions from which to launch highly formalised | A particular type of argumentative youth — it may not shock you to find that the JC was one, once — will take delight in forming abstract and highly artificial positions from which to launch highly formalised denouncements of the views of an anyone holding a contradictory abstract position while opponents to just the same thing back | ||
This used to happen in town squares and speakers corners, and now mainly happens on [[Twitter]]. | This used to happen in town squares and speakers corners, and now mainly happens on [[Twitter]]. | ||
Line 122: | Line 130: | ||
{{ref}} | {{ref}} | ||
{{c|Big ideas}} | {{c|Big ideas}} | ||
<references /> |
Revision as of 21:26, 6 April 2022
|
James P. Carse: Finite and Infinite Games: A Vision of Life as Play and Possibility (1986)
“It wasn’t infinity in fact. Infinity itself looks flat and uninteresting. Looking up into the night sky is looking into infinity — distance is incomprehensible and therefore meaningless. The chamber into which the aircar emerged was anything but infinite, it was just very very very big, so big that it gave the impression of infinity far better than infinity itself.”
Ostensibly, Finite and Infinite Games is a 40-year-old tract of cod philosophy from an obscure religious studies professor. It might well have silted into the geological record — somewhere between Erich von Däniken and Francis Fukuyama — i.e., destined never to be heard from again until it is recycled for peat but having been picked up by life-coach to the LinkedIn generation, Simon Sinek[1] it is having a fertile third age, and when minds as luminous as Stewart Brand’s speak reverently of it, it seems there is life above the daisies for a little while yet. Hope so.
The central idea is this: there are two types of “games” in the world: “finite” ones — zero-sum competitions played with the intention of winning — and “infinite” ones, played with the intention of continuing the play. Finite games are from Mars, via Thomas Hobbes; infinite ones from Venus, via Adam Smith.[2]
In any case to draw this distinction is to use the word “game” in conflicting senses.
A finite game is, in the narrow sense, a contest: fixed rules, fixed boundaries in time and space, an agreed objective and, usually, a winner and a loser. For example, a football game, boxing match, a dog-fight or a board game: notably both chess and go are finite games.
An infinite game is more like a “language game”: no fixed rules, boundaries, or teams; participants can agree change rules or roles as they see fit to help play to continue. For example, a market, a community, a business, a team or a scientific paradigm. These are (Q.E.D.) nebulous arrangements, of course, but one thing they are definitely not is contests. There are no winners and losers in an infinite game, since the idea is to avoid a final result.
You may play multiple, interlocking, nested finite games at any time, and you can even embed finite games into infinite ones — though, for obvious reasons, not vice versa — so it is important in life not to confuse one’s finite and one’s infinite games. The thrust of Sinek’s book is that much of modern life does confuse them: that when we carry over the metaphors of sport and war into business and politics we are tempted to play infinite games to win — that is, as if they were finite games. This is a category error. We may find ourselves excluded from the game while others carry on. We may find our finite objectives hard to pin down, let alone achieve.
That said, the distinction between the two is less tractable than it at first appears. A football match is finite; a football team is infinite. A team plays each match to defeat its opponent utterly; in the wider league, it needs its opponents to survive and flourish, so it can continue to play against them, and so that there is the realistic prospect of drama (and not merely theatrics) on the field. While a team never wishes to lose any particular match, in the long run it must lose some matches in general, lest there be no drama: spectators and players get bored. No-one wants to be beaten every time. No-one wants to win every time. No-one wants to watch a foregone conclusion. We play finite games in the context of a broader infinite game.
Carse, who died last year, was wilfully aphoristic in his literary style. This is off-putting.[3] He would often write things like:
The paradox of genius exposes us directly to the dynamic of open reciprocity, for if you are the genius of what you say to me, I am the genius of what I hear you say. What you say originally I can hear only originally. As you surrender the sound on your lips, I surrender the sound in my ear.
Now this is important, but it would have been better — or, at least, more fathomable — had he explained better what he means by this. That said, this passage assigns as much credit for successful communication to the listener as to the speaker, so perhaps this is the very point. Maybe Carse meant to leave room for listeners to make what they will of his mystic runes. In any case, making head or tail of Carse’s cryptic aphorisms is a kind of infinite game of its own — one that Mr. Sinek is playing pretty well. So, let us join in.
Carse invites us to reframe activities we might see as existential struggles instead as opportunities to build a different future: all it requires is players who are skilled at the infinite game. To do this he sets up a number of dualities:
“Training” versus “education”
“To be prepared against surprise is to be trained. To be prepared for surprise is to be educated.”
Players of finite games train, but do not need education. A master tactician works out moves, devises playbooks, and solves equations for them, presenting all to the players for ingestion and later regurgitation.
All being well, by clinical execution, players overcome their opposition. The team that wins is the one that executes the master plan most effectively. Players should not improvise, for that risks upsetting the master plan. A player’s judgment is limited to selecting which part of the master plan to execute, when and in response to what. Preparation is everything. The idea is to eliminate surprise by having, as far as possible, worked out all possible permutations in advance, and where computing all possible outcomes is not possible, to have computed more possible outcomes than your opponent.
This is the modernist, computerised model of operation: fast, cheap, accurate calculation. The last thing you want is variability, or a player using her initiative: that can ruin everything.
This strategy works where all parameters are fixed and all possible outcomes at least knowable in theory — zero-sum games, simple systems, football matches — but does not always work in the dancing landscapes of complex adaptive systems. If you prepared for chess, your work will be for naught if the game morphs into draughts — or, just as likely, cookery, music, or electronics. Here, instead of eliminating surprise, you equip yourself to deal with it: you need not answers but tools, heuristics and a facility with metaphor.
“Power” versus “strength”
““A powerful person is one who brings the past to an outcome, settling all its unresolved issues. A strong person is one who carries the past into the future, showing that none of its issues is capable of resolution. Power is concerned with what has already happened; strength with what has yet to happen. Power is finite in amount, strength cannot be measured because it is an opening and not a closing act. Power refers to the freedom persons have within limits, strength to the freedoms persons have with limits.
Power will always be restricted to a relatively small number of selected persons. Anyone can be strong.”[4]”
It is fashionable to speak loosely about “power” in our time — much of critical theory is a manifesto against the violence power structures do to the marginalised — and Carse’s distinction between “power” and “strength” reminds us to exercise care.
Sure, social hierarchies can be pernicious, where operated by those engaged in a fight to the death, but most people are not. Critical theories themselves are paradigms — social hierarchies of just this kind. Those who who favour any form of communal organisation more developed that flapping around in primordial sludge will concede that social arrangements don’t have to be destructive: they can be constructive, enabling, levers to prosperity and betterment for everyone who wants it. If we call such a centralised, curated, defended store of knowledge for sharing a “strength structure” it does not sound so ominous.
“Strength is paradoxical. I am not strong because I can force others to do what I wish as a result of my play with them, but because I can allow them to do what they wish in the course of my play with them.”
“Society” versus “culture”
“Society they understand as the sum of those relations that are under some form of public constraint, culture as whatever we do with each other by undirected choice. If society is all that a people fells it must do, culture “is the realm of the variable, free, not necessarily universal, of all that cannot lay claim to compulsive authority”.[5]”
Perhaps Carse would describe a power structure as “society” and a strength structure “culture”. The historic, zero-sum nature of finite games contrasts with the prospective, permissive nature of infinite ones.
Society is finite, bounded, and patriotic: functions to establish a hierarchy, bestowing titles, honorifics and awards — the emblems of past victories in combat, and markers of power —to grant certain participants formal status. One desires the permanence of society because it vouches safe the permanence of one’s titles and prizes.
Culture is infinite, unbounded, endlessly creative and sees its history not as destiny, but tradition: a narrative that has been started but is yet to be completed and that may be adjusted as required. Just as one can can play finite games within the context of an infinite one, so can there be society within culture.
The “theatrical” versus the “dramatic”
Inasmuch as a finite game is intended for conclusion, inasmuch as its roles are scripted and performed for an audience, we shall refer to finite play as theatrical. [...]Inasmuch as infinite players avoid any outcome whatsoever, keeping the future open, making all scripts useless, we shall refer to infinite play as dramatic.Dramatically, one chooses to be a mother. Theatrically one takes on the role of mother.[6]
This is a harder distinction to glom, especially since Carse concedes that during a finite game the action is “provisionally” dramatic, since the players write the script as they go along. But the object of the game is to kill the drama by making the outcome inevitable. So provisional, and hostile, to drama.
The value of artists
A society that wishes to transcend itself and stay in touch with its culture must embrace its “inventors, makers, artists, story-tellers and mythologists”: not those who deal in historical actualities, but who help imagine new possibilities for how the culture might be.[7]Their mode of engagement having no particular intended outcome or conclusion, they can appear hostile to those already holding rank, title or position in society, and who would rather shore up the historical record to validate their victories.
Society is ambivalent towards the dreamers and malcontents who imagine a different order — they once broke Mick Jagger on a wheel; now he’s a peer of the realm — but they operate not by directly confronting the established order, but by sketching out an imagined alternative which eventually takes root.
Original research
There are many resonances here with some of the JC’s other favourite big ideas.
“Complicated” versus “complex”
Finite games are complicated.
Complicated systems require interaction with autonomous agents whose specific behaviour is beyond the observer’s control, and might be intended to defeat the observer’s objective, but whose range of behaviour is deterministic, rule-bound and known and can be predicted in advance, and where the observer’s observing behaviour does not itself interfere with the essential equilibrium of the system.
You know you have a complicated system when it cleaves to a comprehensive set of axioms and rules, and thus it is a matter of making sure that the proper models are being used for the situation at hand. Chess and Alpha Go are complicated, but not complex, systems. So are most sports. You can “force-solve” them, at least in theory.
Complicated systems benefit from skilled management and some expertise to operate: a good chess player will do better than a poor one, and clearly a skilled, fit footballer can execute a plan better than a wheezy novice — but in the right hands and given good instructions even a mediocre player can usually manage without catastrophe. While success will be partly a function of user’s skill and expertise, a bad player with a good plan may defeat a skilled player with a bad one.
Given enough processing power, complicated systems are predictable, determinative and calculable. They’re tame, not wicked problems.
Infinite games are complex.
Complex systems present as “wicked problems”. They are dynamic, unbounded, incomplete, contradictory and constantly changing. They comprise an indefinite set of subcomponents that interact with each other and the environment in unexpected, non-linear ways. They are thus unpredictable, chaotic and “insoluble” — no algorithm can predict how they will behave in all circumstances. Probabilistic models may work passably well most of the time, but the times where statistical models fail may be exactly the times you really wish they didn’t, as Long Term Capital Management would tell you. Complex systems may comprise many other simple, complicated and indeed complex systems, but their interaction with each other will be a whole other thing. So while you may manage the simple and complicated sub-systems effectively with algorithms, checklists, and playbooks — and may manage tthe system on normal times, you remain at risk to “tail events” in abnormal circumstances. You cannot eliminate this risk: accidents in complex systems are inevitable — hence “normal”, in Charles Perrow’s argot. However well you manage a complex system it remains innately unpredictable.
“Historic” versus “prospective”
Many distinctions between finite and infinite games boil down to their historical perspective: those that look backwards, concerning themselves with what has already been established and laid down — as agreed rules, formal boundaries and limited time periods for resolution necessarily do — will tend to be finite in nature; those that are open-ended, forward looking, and indeterminate — concerned with what has yet to happen, and is necessarily unknown, are infinite.
Let me throw in some original research here: historically-focused games are fine: there is no harm and much reward to be had from a game of football, as long as everyone understands the “theatricality” of what is going on; but to apply finite, backward-looking techniques to the “resolution” of infinite scenarios — necessarily forward-looking, indeterminate problems (in that you don’t even know that there is a problem, let alone what it is) is where you will get into bother.
It is deceptive in that finite techniques may work perfectly well much of the time, because even infinite environments largely function by reference to established order, existing rules and what is already known: they look, for the most part, like finite games — it’s just that they don’t have to, and are liable to change without notice. As long as they behave themselves, a finite approach is efficient, effective, centrally controllable and provides consistency and certainty. This is why thought leaders are so fond of sporting metaphors.
This, we think, is just an other way of noting that the middle of a normal distribution resembles the middle of a “fat-tailed” distribution and the same approaches will work passably well for both, as long as the events fall within the middle, which for the most part they do.
“Formal” versus “substantive”
We have argued elsewhere that the great curse of modernity is the primacy of form over substance. In finite games the distinction between the two can be trivial; in an infinite game it is not.
In a backward-looking, proven, data-complete universe, substance is simply a specific articulation of form. The universe is solved; there is an exclusive optimal move and it can be derived from first principle. Substance follows from — is dependent on — form. Form is an axiom; substance is its articulation with numbers. If you have right equation — that is to say, if you follow the right form — you will get the right answer. Indeed, without the right form you have almost no chance of getting the right answer, and none at all of knowing that you have it. This depends on the universe being bounded, all rules determined, all knowns known. It depends, therefore, on the conditions existing for a finite game.
Where the universe is not bounded, where rules are unknown or changeable, where unknowns swamp knowns[8] — where the game is infinite — substance is not a function of form. There are no equations, axioms or formulae to follow when interacting with complex adaptive systems. It will be tempting to rely on formulae that tend to work most of the time — the Black Scholes option pricing model works most of the time, at least until it does not — but this is a lazy and, at the limit, dangerous, economy. We need a different approach. Instead of the trained — those best equipped to carry out complicated instructions — we need the educated: those best equipped to observe, orient, decide and act. These people are necessarily skilled, experienced and therefore expensive.
Top-down versus bottom-up
You know, man, when I was a young man in high school
You believe it or not, I wanted to play football for the coach
And all those older guys
They said that he was mean and cruel, but you know
I wanted to play football for the coach.
- Lou Reed, Coney Island Baby
Finite games as execution of the master plan
Finite games favour top-down game management, with central homunculus instilling in players a defined set of pre-formulated tactics: a coach to formulate them and a captain to see they are executed. Infinite games are bottom up: every player must continually assess her environment and work out what to do based on the information she currently has. Here a “coach” is little more than a central coordinator supplying information and resources to help the players make their own tactical decisions as the need arises.
In a predefined contest, form dominates substance: we should concentrate our resources at the centre, formulate rules, work out algorithms and devise playbooks, since if we get this right, success is a matter of execution, and “failure” comes from shortcomings in execution of the plan.
This has a few implications: firstly, it means the brilliant minds belong at the top of the organisation: they do the most inspired thinking.
Secondly, it means there is no more sacred quest than the creation of excellent process. Our most talented personnel are those who can write and maintain formal rules.
Thirdly, it means those at the edges of the organisation whose job is not to formulate policy but to follow it — those who must put the leadership’s plans and algorithms into practice — must not think: they must, so far as possible, just follow instructions: quickly, flawlessly, cheaply. They should act like automatons. If you are in a finite game environment, the last thing you want your players to do is improvise, or make things up as they go along: that will upset the carefully formulated plan. Players must not just act like machines: ideally, players would be machines: cheap, reliable and fungible.
Those with an interest in modern corporate management philosophy might recognise this disposition. It is the one that recommends that those who carry out the firm’s day-to-day business and interact with its clients should be juniorised, if they cannot be outsourced, if they cannot be automated — those who formulate strategy and policy and who watch from the Gods should be feted, lionised, and rewarded.
Infinite games as virtuoso improvisation
Infinite games favour virtuoso performances in the field: in a wicked environment cheap, quick, accurate machines are no use, and the infrastructure they need to ensure they continue working may get in the way. Rather than being elaborate, internal infrastructure should be simple, robust and permissive — enabling communication, facilitating dynamic reallocation of resources, but fundamentally organising the architecture to empower quick and effective decision-making in the field. Seeing as the idea is not to win but to continue, conferring discretion upon those at the edge of the organisation who must engage with the complex adaptive system outside is not necessarily catastrophic as long as the individuals are experienced experts: they must not act like machines, and empowered — trusted to deal with unfolding situations as they perceive them. The ongoing prosperity of the organisation is an emergent property of the behaviour of these subject matter experts. This is quite the opposite model: here the greatest value is provided at the edges of the organisation. The bottom-up model: laissez-faire; invisible hand; evolutionary.
As single-round and iterated prisoner’s dilemmas
A finite game can be part of an infinite game but not vice versa. One could regard a sports franchise an an organisation playing an infinite game through the medium of finite games: here its immediate interests in each distinct match — to comprehensively, theatrically, thrash the opposition — is tempered by its wider interest to keep the infinite game going by creating a compelling sporting contest in which there is the drama that one might not, at any time, win. To carry on that wider, infinite game, one’s opponents must not only survive, but flourish to the point where they can and will beat you in a finite game, thus supplying theatre if not really drama: an unbeatable team is unsatisfying for winners, losers and spectators alike.
And here we wonder a little about the commutability of infinite games into finite ones: sporting matches are like single round prisoner’s dilemmas: zero-sum in a way that recommends only outright domination.
Problem cases
The Christians, atheists and their interminable games
A particular type of argumentative youth — it may not shock you to find that the JC was one, once — will take delight in forming abstract and highly artificial positions from which to launch highly formalised denouncements of the views of an anyone holding a contradictory abstract position while opponents to just the same thing back
This used to happen in town squares and speakers corners, and now mainly happens on Twitter.
These games account for much of modern public discourse, but do not easily fall into Carse’s rubric. Each player’s ostensible goal is to win by proving definitively that his opponent is wrong.
This therefore has the appearance of a run-of-the-mill two-hander finite game: fixed rules, fixed sides and ostensibly clear success criteria — except that it is nothing of the kind, as there is no time boundary and the named of the game is to keep going which, as long as you're opponent still had breath in him, you can happily do, as each side wittingly, if not willingly, supplies intellectual straw men for his opponent to carry on knocking down.
Axiomatic that neither player will ever accept any opponent’s argument as a decisive, or even wounding, blow, and play will continue without conclusion, to the great delight of all participants (though it is a delight which presents as studied outrage at what the opponent is saying, but is really nothing of the kind) and the profound ennuyeux of everyone else.
There are many flavours of these games — they are not finite or infinite so much as interminable: left versus right; Brexit versus Remain, anything involving critical theory or social justice, religion, political orientation or football team primacy.
See also
References
- ↑ The Infinite Game by Simon Sinek (2019) (see here).
- ↑ I am told, incidentally, that it will not to to be “guided by white men who died in the 17th and 18th centuries.” I don’t think it will do to be guided by people who say such inane things.
- ↑ Notably, Carse’s speaking style is much less cryptic and talks he gave about the infinite game concept are worth checking out. See for example his talk to the Long Now Foundation: Religious Wars in Light of the Infinite Game.
- ↑ Carse, §29.
- ↑ Finite and Infinite Games Ch. 2 (citing Carl Jacob Christoph Burckhardt).
- ↑ Section 15.
- ↑ Unhelpfully, Carse calls these people “poietai” — from Plato’s expression, a label hardly calculated to make his work more penetrable.
- ↑ All data is from the past. Seeing as there is an infinite amount of data from the future, the portion of the available data we have is, effectively, nil.