Stakeholder capitalism: Difference between revisions

From The Jolly Contrarian
Jump to navigation Jump to search
No edit summary
No edit summary
Line 1: Line 1:
{{a|devil|{{image|Water scarcity|png|Or you could spend more time managing your loan book? Just a thought.}}{{image|Stakeholder capitalism|png|}} }}=== Adam Smith’s Dangerous Idea ===
{{a|devil|{{image|Water scarcity|png|Or you could spend more time managing your loan book? Just a thought.}}{{image|Stakeholder capitalism|png|}} }}=== Adam Smith’s Dangerous Idea ===
Once upon a time, not long ago, [[shareholder]]s were opaque, sacred beings. Ineffable, invisible, immortal and divine: to their improving ends the company’s mortal [[agent|stewards]] twitched their every fibre.
Once upon a time, not long ago, [[shareholder]]s were opaque, sacred beings. Ineffable, invisible, immortal and divine: to their improving ends the company’s mortal [[agent|stewards]] twitched their every fibre.


This ''[[Shareholder capitalism|will to shareholder return]]'' sprang from [[Adam Smith]]’s brow and his [[invisible hand]]:
This ''[[Shareholder capitalism|will to shareholder return]]'' sprang from [[Adam Smith]]’s [[invisible hand]]:
{{quote|“...Though the sole end which they propose from the labours of all the thousands whom they employ, be the gratification of their own vain and insatiable desires, they divide with the poor the produce of all their improvements...They are led by an invisible hand to make nearly the same distribution of the necessaries of life, which would have been made, had the earth been divided into equal portions among all its inhabitants, ''and thus without intending it, without knowing it, advance the interest of the society, and afford means to the multiplication of the species''”<ref>''The Theory of Moral Sentiments'' (1759) Part IV, Chapter 1.</ref>}}
{{quote|“...Though the sole end which they propose from the labours of all the thousands whom they employ, be the gratification of their own vain and insatiable desires, they divide with the poor the produce of all their improvements...They are led by an invisible hand to make nearly the same distribution of the necessaries of life, which would have been made, had the earth been divided into equal portions among all its inhabitants, ''and thus without intending it, without knowing it, advance the interest of the society, and afford means to the multiplication of the species''”<ref>''The Theory of Moral Sentiments'' (1759) Part IV, Chapter 1.</ref>}}


This was, a ''breathtaking'' insight; no less [[Darwin’s Dangerous Idea|dangerous]] than [[Darwin’s Dangerous Idea|Charles Darwin]]’s: from collected, unconcerted, unfettered, selfish actions [[emerges]] optimised community welfare.
This was, a ''breathtaking'' insight; no less [[Darwin’s Dangerous Idea|dangerous]] than [[Darwin’s Dangerous Idea|Charles Darwin]]’s: from collected, disorganised, unfettered, selfish actions [[emerges]] optimised community welfare.


It is, in fact, the same idea: a recurring, algorithmic process can ''reduce'' the [[entropy]] in a system. Creation out of chaos. This is is as “dangerous” to Newton as to God. Anyway, I digress.
It is, in fact, the same idea: a recurring, algorithmic process can ''reduce'' the [[entropy]] in a system. Creation comes from chaos. This is is as “dangerous” to Newton as it was to God. Anyway, I digress.


The limited liability corporation is the philosophical embodiment of that idea.  ''Look after the [[shareholder]]s, and society will look after itself.''
The [[Limited liability company|limited liability corporation]] is the philosophical embodiment of that idea.  ''Look after the [[shareholder]]s, and society will look after itself.''


Pursuing only its shareholders’ enrichment would make the corporation preternaturally nimble, responsive to society’s demands: best incentivised, so the theory had it, to allocate capital where the community most needed it. This is a practical philosophy: here actions speak louder than words.
[[Shareholder capitalism]] has the advantage of easy performance measurement: you can evaluate every impulse, every decision, every project, every transaction against a single, simple yardstick: ''was it in the [[Shareholder|shareholders]]’ best interest?''


“Compare this,” declared proselytes, “with the disasters of central planning, five-year plans, great leaps forward and so on.” These are theoretical philosophies. They are robust in concept, but flimsy upon contact with the grim realities of human behaviour.
Shareholders’ interest, in turn, could also be measured along a single, simple dimension: ''profit''. Nothing else mattered. The [[professional-managerial class]], and their endemic [[agency problem]], were hemmed in: you can’t hide from after-tax profit.


[[Shareholder capitalism]] had its advantages, to be sure: not least of which was easy performance measurement: one could evaluate every impulse, every decision, every project, every transaction against a single, simple yardstick: ''was this in the [[Shareholder|shareholders]]’ best interest?''
Pursuing only its shareholders’ enrichment, therefore, would make a corporation preternaturally nimble, responsive to society’s demands: best incentivised, so the theory had it, to allocate capital where the community most needed it. This is a ''practical'' philosophy: here, actions speak louder than words.


Shareholders’ interest, in turn, could be measured along a single, simple dimension: ''profit''. Nothing else mattered. The [[professional-managerial class]], and their endemic [[agency problem]], were hemmed in: you can’t hide from after-tax profit.
“Compare this,” declared followers of the Chicago School, “with the disasters of central planning, five-year plans, great leaps forward and so on.” These are ''theoretical'' philosophies: robust in concept but flimsy upon contact with the grim realities of human behaviour.


=== Stakeholder capitalism ===
=== Stakeholder capitalism ===
Well, that was then.  
Well, that was then.  


Enlightenment orthodoxy has fallen from grace. Milton Friedman is out of fashion. The narrative has changed. Unalloyed selfishness<ref>This seems ironic, in so self-obsessed a time as this, but read it as “unalloyed selfishness by someone other than me” and it makes perfect sense.</ref> has become intolerable.
Enlightenment orthodoxy has fallen from grace. Milton Friedman has been cast from heaven. The narrative has changed. Unalloyed selfishness<ref>This seems ironic, in so self-obsessed a time as this, but read it as “unalloyed selfishness by someone other than me” and it makes perfect sense.</ref> has become intolerable.
 
Dangerous, even: in 2003, legal academic Joel Bakan put the argument that since a [[Legal person|corporation]]’s sole statutory motive is the short-term enrichment of its owners, it has the clinical characteristics of a ''psychopath''.<ref>Joel Bakan, ''The Corporation: The Pathological Pursuit of Profit and Power'' (2003)</ref>
 
Things have only got worse since for Adam Smith’s conviction in the [[Emergence|emergent]] goodness of shareholder profit.
 
We are cancelling and redrawing the world: let us cancel and redraw our corporate aspirations too. Shareholder capitalism is, by design, venal, selfish and riven with [[Unconscious bias|bias]]. Its stampede for profit demonstrates an abject want of care for everyone else.
 
And so it has come to pass: “''stakeholder'' capitalism” has displaced [[shareholder capitalism]]. [[Wall Street|Gordon Gekko]] is out. Arif Naqvi is in.
 
We, the planet, ask corporations to orient themselves toward ''all'' their “stakeholders” — customers, [[creditor]]s, suppliers, [[employee]]s, the community, the [[Environmental, social and corporate governance|environment]], the marginalised multitudes that suffer invisibly under the awful [[Externality|externalities]] of industry ''and'' — last, but not least! — shareholders.


''Corporations must not profit at the expense of the wider world''.
''Dangerous'', even. In 2003, legal academic Joel Bakan put the argument that, since a [[Legal person|corporation]]’s sole statutory motive is the short-term enrichment of its owners, it has the clinical characteristics of a ''psychopath''.<ref>Joel Bakan, ''The Corporation: The Pathological Pursuit of Profit and Power'' (2003)</ref> Since then, things have only got worse since for Adam Smith’s conviction.


This view seems so modern, so [[empathetic]] and so ''right'' — so ''fit for [[Twitter]]'' — that it is hard to see how anyone can ever have thought otherwise.
We are cancelling and redrawing the world: let us cancel and redraw our corporate aspirations too. The profit motive is, by design, venal, selfish and riven with [[Unconscious bias|bias]]. Its stampede for profit demonstrates an abject want of care for everyone, and every thing, else. And so it has come to pass: “''stakeholder'' capitalism” has displaced [[shareholder capitalism]]. The wider world is the constituency. Greed is not good.


But still, this is a striking reversal.  
We, the planet, demand that corporations to orient themselves towards ''all'' their “stakeholders” — customers, [[creditor]]s, suppliers, [[employee]]s, the community, the [[Environmental, social and corporate governance|environment]], the marginalised multitudes that suffer invisibly under the awful [[Externality|externalities]] of industry ''and'' — last, but not least! — shareholders. ''Corporations must not profit at the expense of the wider world''.


Even the Business Roundtable is getting in on the act: in 2019, it “redefined the purpose of a corporation” away from ''the outright pursuit of profit'' towards ''promoting an economy that serves all Americans''.
This view seems so modern, so [[empathetic]] and so ''right'' that it is hard to see how anyone can ever have thought otherwise. But still, this is a striking reversal for the free market fundamentalists. Even the Business Roundtable is getting in on the act: in 2019, it “redefined the purpose of a corporation” away from ''the outright pursuit of profit'' towards ''promoting an economy that serves all Americans''.


{{Quote|“It affirms the essential role corporations can play in improving our society,” said Alex Gorsky,<ref>No relation to ''that'' [[Good luck, Mr. Gorsky|Mr. Gorsky]], as far as we know.</ref> Chairman and CEO of Johnson & Johnson and Chair of the Roundtable’s Corporate Governance Committee,<ref>Not trying to be funny or anything, but is being Chairman ''and'' CEO really the best example for a chair of a corporate governance committee to set?</ref> “when [[CEO|CEOs]] are truly committed to meeting the needs of all [[stakeholder]]s.”}}
{{Quote|“It affirms the essential role corporations can play in improving our society,” said Alex Gorsky, Chairman and CEO of Johnson & Johnson and Chair of the Roundtable’s Corporate Governance Committee,<ref>Is being Chairman ''and'' CEO really the best example for a chair of a corporate governance committee to set?</ref> “when [[CEO|CEOs]] are truly committed to meeting the needs of all [[stakeholder]]s.”}}


But, first principles. There is theory and there is practice. Practical systems do not always make for good theoretical philosophy. Philosophical theories do not always yield practical systems.
But, first principles. There is ''theory'' and there is ''practice''. Practical systems do not always make for good theory. Theoretical philosophies do not always yield practical systems.


Stakeholder capitalism ''codifies'' the [[agency problem]]. It diffuses the executive’s accountability for anything the corporation does, putting the [[professional-managerial class]] beyond the reproach of the one stakeholder group with the necessary means, justification and consensus to call it out: their [[Shareholder|shareholders]].
Stakeholder capitalism ''codifies'' the [[agency problem]]. It diffuses an executive’s accountability for anything the corporation does, putting the [[professional-managerial class]] beyond the reproach of the one stakeholder group with the necessary means, justification and consensus to call it out: their [[Shareholder|shareholders]].


===Stakeholder capitalism as disguised ''shareholder'' capitalism===
===Stakeholder capitalism as disguised ''shareholder'' capitalism===
Line 63: Line 54:
Under Joel Bakan’s theory, remember, it is not the ''shareholders'' who are psychopaths, but the [[corporation]]s they own, as distinct [[Legal personality|legal person]]s.
Under Joel Bakan’s theory, remember, it is not the ''shareholders'' who are psychopaths, but the [[corporation]]s they own, as distinct [[Legal personality|legal person]]s.


The shareholders are only a ''motivation'' for the corporate pathology. Which is just as well, because shareholders come from all walks of life: through our retirement plans, 401(k)s and ISAs, ''we'' are the ultimate shareholders: [[diverse]] in every conceivable dimension, bar one.
The shareholders are only a ''motivation'' for the corporate pathology. This is just as well, because shareholders come from all walks of life: through our retirement plans, 401(k)s and ISAs, ''we'' are the ultimate shareholders: we are [[diverse]] in every conceivable dimension, bar one.


Shareholders don’t have to know each other, like each other or care less about each other. On any other topic, their aspirations and priorities will jar, clatter and conflict. If you put them in a room to discuss anything ''but'' their shareholding, you should not be surprised if a fight breaks out.
We the shareholders don’t have to know each other, like each other or care less about each other. On any other topic, our aspirations and priorities will jar, clatter and conflict. If you put a group of random shareholders in a room to discuss anything ''but'' their shareholding, you should not be surprised if a fight breaks out.


But on that one subject, they are ''necessarily'' aligned: each will say, “whatever else I care about in my life, members of the board, know this: ''I expect you to maximise my return''.”
But on that one subject, they are ''necessarily'' aligned: each will say, “whatever else I care about in my life, members of the board, know this: ''I expect you to maximise my return''.”


=== About that return===
=== About that return===
Now you might argue that, since we are all shareholders in one way or another, stakeholder capitalism is no more than paying attention to shareholders’ ''wider'' interests and not just their monetary ones. This way, polar bears get a look in, but only if that is in the shareholders’ wider interest.
Now you might argue that, since we are all shareholders in one way or another, stakeholder capitalism is no more than paying attention to shareholders’ ''wider'' interests and not just their monetary ones. This way, polar bears get a look in, but only where shareholders care about polar bears.


But that isn’t ''stakeholder'' capitalism: that’s just a debased version of ''shareholder'' capitalism. It replaces shareholders’ ''monetary'' interests for their ''moral'' ones, along the way substituting the shareholders’ moral judgments — which are certain to conflict— with the Board’s.
But that isn’t ''stakeholder'' capitalism: that’s just a debased version of ''shareholder'' capitalism. It replaces shareholders’ ''monetary'' interests for their ''moral'' ones, along the way substituting the individual shareholders’ moral judgments — which, to repeat, are bound to conflict— with the Board’s.


''That is not the deal''. The Board are the shareholders’ ''servants''. They don’t get to moralise on the shareholders’ behalves.
''That is not the deal''. The Board are the shareholders’ ''servants''. They don’t get to moralise on the owner’s behalf.


Besides, to ditch this narrow financial interest is to miss the single clinching insight. Shareholders may differ about how to prioritise polar bears. They probably do. They don’t differ about the value of [[cash]].  
Besides, to ditch this narrow financial interest is to miss the single clinching insight. Shareholders may disagree about polar bears. They probably do. They won’t differ about the value of [[cash]].  


''As long as it is all about return, there can be no arguments.''
''As long as it is all about return, there can be no arguments.''
Line 92: Line 83:


In 2018 the Economic Policy Institute mapped CEO compensation against worker compensation and the performance of the S&P500 since 1965.<ref>https://www.epi.org/publication/ceo-compensation-2018/</ref>  It gives a pretty good picture of how shareholders, workers and executives are doing relative to each other.   
In 2018 the Economic Policy Institute mapped CEO compensation against worker compensation and the performance of the S&P500 since 1965.<ref>https://www.epi.org/publication/ceo-compensation-2018/</ref>  It gives a pretty good picture of how shareholders, workers and executives are doing relative to each other.   
{| class="wikitable"
{|
|+EPI Comparison: Employees, Shareholders and Executives 1965-2018
!Stakeholder
!Stakeholder
!Annual change
!Annual change
Line 112: Line 102:
How do you arbitrate between creditors and the local community? Between the environment and customers? Between penguins and polar bears? On whose say?
How do you arbitrate between creditors and the local community? Between the environment and customers? Between penguins and polar bears? On whose say?


And who ''are'' these stakeholders for whose wellbeing the corporation is suddenly guardian? Shareholders’ names and interests, after all are set out on a register. There is no corresponding ranked list of constituents, interest groups, factions. The priorities, narratives and moral imperatives of “the world at large” are indeterminate.<ref>Those railing at this idea and not persuaded by a cursory glance at the day’s newspapers are invited to consider the works of Kant, Mill, Hobbes, Hume, Smith, Nietzsche, Nozick, Wollstonecraft, Warnock, Butler, Rawls, hooks and Marx and return with a concise summary. </ref>
And who ''are'' these stakeholders for whose wellbeing the corporation is suddenly guardian? Shareholders’ names and interests, after all are set out on a register. There is no corresponding ranked list of constituents, interest groups, factions. The priorities, narratives and moral imperatives of “the world at large” are indeterminate. Those railing at this idea and not persuaded by a cursory glance at the day’s newspapers are invited to consider the works of Kant, Mill, Hobbes, Hume, Smith, Nietzsche, Nozick, Wollstonecraft, Warnock, Butler, Rawls, hooks and Marx and return with a concise summary.


Even if you know ''who'' they are, how do you ''what'' — beyond having as much of your soda as you can make, as cheap as you can sell it — your stakeholders’ interests are?<ref>There is a hand-wavy argument that executives should have in mind the “best interests of the community” and not anyone’s selfish needs and wants. But who knows what that is? How does a moral agenda determined by the corporate executive class — mainly white, ageing, cis-gendered, post colonial men, in case it at slipped anyone’s attention — improve on no moral agenda at all?
Even if you know ''who'' they are, how do you know ''what'' — beyond having as much of your soda as you can make, as cheap as you can sell it — your stakeholders’ interests are? Whose interests have priority? ''Why''?
</ref> Whose interests have priority? ''Why''?  


Now a failure to generate a decent cash return can be blamed on — well, ''anything'' — your success in reducing the number of smokers in the accounts department, or the cash your community outreach team spent on beautifying a local park, or the facilities manager who was twice the going rate but whom you chose for his exemplary anti-modern slavery policy.
Now a failure to generate a decent cash return can be blamed on — well, ''anything'' — your success in reducing the number of smokers in the accounts department, or the cash your community outreach team spent on beautifying a local park, or the facilities manager who was twice the going rate but whom you chose for his exemplary anti-modern slavery policy.


Stakeholder capitalism means an imaginative executive always has an excuse. ''Always''. For ''everything''. To run a company ''for the world at large'' is to run it ''for no-one''. And when a [[professional-managerial class]] of agents can’t work out who ''else’s'' interests to put first, what do we expect them to do?
Stakeholder capitalism means always having an alternative narrative — an ''excuse''. For ''everything''. To run a company ''for the world at large'' is to run it ''for no-one''. And when a [[professional-managerial class]] of agents can’t work out who ''else’s'' interests to put first, whose interests do you think they will naturally choose?


===Are corporations best-placed to look after everyone else’s interests?===
===Are corporations best-placed to look after everyone else’s interests?===

Revision as of 10:23, 9 June 2023

Or you could spend more time managing your loan book? Just a thought.
In which the curmudgeonly old sod puts the world to rights.
Index — Click ᐅ to expand:
Tell me more
Sign up for our newsletter — or just get in touch: for ½ a weekly 🍺 you get to consult JC. Ask about it here.

Adam Smith’s Dangerous Idea

Once upon a time, not long ago, shareholders were opaque, sacred beings. Ineffable, invisible, immortal and divine: to their improving ends the company’s mortal stewards twitched their every fibre.

This will to shareholder return sprang from Adam Smith’s invisible hand:

“...Though the sole end which they propose from the labours of all the thousands whom they employ, be the gratification of their own vain and insatiable desires, they divide with the poor the produce of all their improvements...They are led by an invisible hand to make nearly the same distribution of the necessaries of life, which would have been made, had the earth been divided into equal portions among all its inhabitants, and thus without intending it, without knowing it, advance the interest of the society, and afford means to the multiplication of the species[1]

This was, a breathtaking insight; no less dangerous than Charles Darwin’s: from collected, disorganised, unfettered, selfish actions emerges optimised community welfare.

It is, in fact, the same idea: a recurring, algorithmic process can reduce the entropy in a system. Creation comes from chaos. This is is as “dangerous” to Newton as it was to God. Anyway, I digress.

The limited liability corporation is the philosophical embodiment of that idea. Look after the shareholders, and society will look after itself.

Shareholder capitalism has the advantage of easy performance measurement: you can evaluate every impulse, every decision, every project, every transaction against a single, simple yardstick: was it in the shareholders’ best interest?

Shareholders’ interest, in turn, could also be measured along a single, simple dimension: profit. Nothing else mattered. The professional-managerial class, and their endemic agency problem, were hemmed in: you can’t hide from after-tax profit.

Pursuing only its shareholders’ enrichment, therefore, would make a corporation preternaturally nimble, responsive to society’s demands: best incentivised, so the theory had it, to allocate capital where the community most needed it. This is a practical philosophy: here, actions speak louder than words.

“Compare this,” declared followers of the Chicago School, “with the disasters of central planning, five-year plans, great leaps forward and so on.” These are theoretical philosophies: robust in concept but flimsy upon contact with the grim realities of human behaviour.

Stakeholder capitalism

Well, that was then.

Enlightenment orthodoxy has fallen from grace. Milton Friedman has been cast from heaven. The narrative has changed. Unalloyed selfishness[2] has become intolerable.

Dangerous, even. In 2003, legal academic Joel Bakan put the argument that, since a corporation’s sole statutory motive is the short-term enrichment of its owners, it has the clinical characteristics of a psychopath.[3] Since then, things have only got worse since for Adam Smith’s conviction.

We are cancelling and redrawing the world: let us cancel and redraw our corporate aspirations too. The profit motive is, by design, venal, selfish and riven with bias. Its stampede for profit demonstrates an abject want of care for everyone, and every thing, else. And so it has come to pass: “stakeholder capitalism” has displaced shareholder capitalism. The wider world is the constituency. Greed is not good.

We, the planet, demand that corporations to orient themselves towards all their “stakeholders” — customers, creditors, suppliers, employees, the community, the environment, the marginalised multitudes that suffer invisibly under the awful externalities of industry and — last, but not least! — shareholders. Corporations must not profit at the expense of the wider world.

This view seems so modern, so empathetic and so right that it is hard to see how anyone can ever have thought otherwise. But still, this is a striking reversal for the free market fundamentalists. Even the Business Roundtable is getting in on the act: in 2019, it “redefined the purpose of a corporation” away from the outright pursuit of profit towards promoting an economy that serves all Americans.

“It affirms the essential role corporations can play in improving our society,” said Alex Gorsky, Chairman and CEO of Johnson & Johnson and Chair of the Roundtable’s Corporate Governance Committee,[4] “when CEOs are truly committed to meeting the needs of all stakeholders.”

But, first principles. There is theory and there is practice. Practical systems do not always make for good theory. Theoretical philosophies do not always yield practical systems.

Stakeholder capitalism codifies the agency problem. It diffuses an executive’s accountability for anything the corporation does, putting the professional-managerial class beyond the reproach of the one stakeholder group with the necessary means, justification and consensus to call it out: their shareholders.

Stakeholder capitalism as disguised shareholder capitalism

Maybe that’s what the Business Roundtable meant; maybe not. Maybe they’ve changed their minds. Here’s current chair, Jamie Dimon, quoted in the FT:

“All we’re saying is when we wake up in the morning, what we give a shit about is serving customers, earning their respect, earning their repeat business.”[5]

But that is no reimagining of the fundamental purpose of a corporation: it is just a better view of the old one.

If your customers happen not to be, or care about, polar bears, then no need to lose any sleep about polar bears, and no need to give shit about them when you wake up if you do. Your only decision is “whether me caring about polar bears will make more people buy my stuff, and thereby increase my bottom line”.

This is just shareholder capitalism.

About those shareholders

Under Joel Bakan’s theory, remember, it is not the shareholders who are psychopaths, but the corporations they own, as distinct legal persons.

The shareholders are only a motivation for the corporate pathology. This is just as well, because shareholders come from all walks of life: through our retirement plans, 401(k)s and ISAs, we are the ultimate shareholders: we are diverse in every conceivable dimension, bar one.

We the shareholders don’t have to know each other, like each other or care less about each other. On any other topic, our aspirations and priorities will jar, clatter and conflict. If you put a group of random shareholders in a room to discuss anything but their shareholding, you should not be surprised if a fight breaks out.

But on that one subject, they are necessarily aligned: each will say, “whatever else I care about in my life, members of the board, know this: I expect you to maximise my return.”

About that return

Now you might argue that, since we are all shareholders in one way or another, stakeholder capitalism is no more than paying attention to shareholders’ wider interests and not just their monetary ones. This way, polar bears get a look in, but only where shareholders care about polar bears.

But that isn’t stakeholder capitalism: that’s just a debased version of shareholder capitalism. It replaces shareholders’ monetary interests for their moral ones, along the way substituting the individual shareholders’ moral judgments — which, to repeat, are bound to conflict— with the Board’s.

That is not the deal. The Board are the shareholders’ servants. They don’t get to moralise on the owner’s behalf.

Besides, to ditch this narrow financial interest is to miss the single clinching insight. Shareholders may disagree about polar bears. They probably do. They won’t differ about the value of cash.

As long as it is all about return, there can be no arguments.

The abstraction of value and the important of cash

Long ago, our forebears in ancient Mesopotamia hit upon a way to abstract pure, disembodied value from the relativising commodities and perishable plant, machinery and substrates in which it is usually embedded: they called that abstracted value “money”.

Cash does not go off, cannot be eaten, and does not depend for its value on anything else. Cash is abstract value.

Hence its value as a yardstick for corporate performance. In discharging their sacred duty, those stewarding the affairs of corporation could not have clearer instructions: should the return they generate, valued in folding green stuff, not pass muster, there will be no excuses.

There is no dog who can eat a chief executive’s homework, no looking on the bright side because employee engagement numbers are up, no consolation to be taken in the popularity of the company’s float in the May Day parade: if the annual return disappoints, members of the executive board, expect to get shot.

“But surely, JC, the shareholders need no protection from chief executive officers! It is the disenfranchised underclass at the margins of society who must be protected!”

In 2018 the Economic Policy Institute mapped CEO compensation against worker compensation and the performance of the S&P500 since 1965.[6] It gives a pretty good picture of how shareholders, workers and executives are doing relative to each other.

Stakeholder Annual change
Employee +2.5%
Shareholder +8.5%
CEO +35%

So, before we cast the poor shareholders’ interests to the wind, ask this: by switching to stakeholder capitalism, who benefits?

Stakeholder capitalism means never having to say you’re sorry

When shareholders hold the whip hand, an executive’s goal is simple. Make money. That clarity of purpose evaporates the moment the executive’s remit expands. Multiple stakeholders means multiple interests, which must conflict.

How do you arbitrate between creditors and the local community? Between the environment and customers? Between penguins and polar bears? On whose say?

And who are these stakeholders for whose wellbeing the corporation is suddenly guardian? Shareholders’ names and interests, after all are set out on a register. There is no corresponding ranked list of constituents, interest groups, factions. The priorities, narratives and moral imperatives of “the world at large” are indeterminate. Those railing at this idea and not persuaded by a cursory glance at the day’s newspapers are invited to consider the works of Kant, Mill, Hobbes, Hume, Smith, Nietzsche, Nozick, Wollstonecraft, Warnock, Butler, Rawls, hooks and Marx and return with a concise summary.

Even if you know who they are, how do you know what — beyond having as much of your soda as you can make, as cheap as you can sell it — your stakeholders’ interests are? Whose interests have priority? Why?

Now a failure to generate a decent cash return can be blamed on — well, anything — your success in reducing the number of smokers in the accounts department, or the cash your community outreach team spent on beautifying a local park, or the facilities manager who was twice the going rate but whom you chose for his exemplary anti-modern slavery policy.

Stakeholder capitalism means always having an alternative narrative — an excuse. For everything. To run a company for the world at large is to run it for no-one. And when a professional-managerial class of agents can’t work out who else’s interests to put first, whose interests do you think they will naturally choose?

Are corporations best-placed to look after everyone else’s interests?

Yes, customers are your stakeholders, and they have an interest how you conduct your business, but — at least in a healthy marketplace — they can control that a lot more directly, regularly and effectively than can shareholders: they can buy something else. You can only maximise shareholder return by persuading lots of customers to buy your stuff.

As a vox pop in Bakan’s film puts it: “If you don’t like Pepsi-Cola, Bank of America, well, if you don't like what they do, don’t use ’em. That’s the way I see the people’s power is.”

By contrast, shareholders are a bit like voters in a representative democracy: their main weapon is their power to sell their stock; beyond that, there’s the AGM, and unless you’re an institutional money manager, don’t expect anyone in the C suite to be massively bothered how you vote.

Employees — especially those in the executive suite — have all the power they need to influence the company. They are there, every day, making every decision.

Of course the disenfranchised minorities at the margins of our community need a voice. As we argue elsewhere, an optimal society is pluralistic, tolerant, defends those at the margins and, all other things being equal, prefers their interests when they conflict with a majority that is perfectly able to look after itself. But the question is not whether to protect their interests, but how. There are plenty of better ways than through stakeholder capitalism: representative democracy, for a start.

But even so, beyond their shareholding, shareholders are not monolithic investing homunculi: they are ordinary people with disposable income. If they want to beautify the inner city, save polar bears or fight water scarcity, they can do that directly. There are charities whose very mandate is to agitate for just that. That is a far better way to allocate capital. It puts control in the investors’ hands, where it should be. Investors do not need to channel their charitable activity through the medium of their equity portfolio. And why would they?

We cannot fathom the moral agenda, if there even is one behind an investor’s decision to invest in a bank stock. And are Bank executives really best advised to draw attention to the moral qualities of their organisations? Who knows if bank shareholders care about water scarcity or polar bears? But if the alternatives are “assume shareholders mainly want a capital return, and do that” or “let the chief executive decide what her shareholders’ moral priorities should be”, then it is not a difficult choice.

Banks should prioritise prudent lending standards and timely risk management. Corporates should deliver goods and services to their customers for more than it costs to produce them. Companies should stick to their knitting. Governments, NGOs, supra-nationals and dedicated charities with resources, expertise and focus can deal with water scarcity. If bank shareholders care about water scarcity, they can give their disposable resources to water scarcity specialists. That is surely a better way of doing it than buying bank stocks.

About those executives

Professor Bakan’s proposition that a disembodied pile of papers is intrinsically psychopathic is a bit far-fetched. The idea that the collected shareholders of the world’s companies are all psychopaths is even more far fetched. Well, if it isn’t we are well and truly doomed, because that is all of us.

But the idea that, of the tiny, feral class who elbow their way into the executive suites of the world’s listed companies, an outsized portion has a sociopathic element to their personalities? We do not find that especially far-fetched at all. Now — if we allow for a cynical moment that it might be true — ask yourself this: is it wise to delegate responsibility for working out our moral priorities to a small group of entitled people with a plausibly heightened propensity towards psychopathic behaviour? For isn’t that what stakeholder capitalism essentially advocates?

See also

References

  1. The Theory of Moral Sentiments (1759) Part IV, Chapter 1.
  2. This seems ironic, in so self-obsessed a time as this, but read it as “unalloyed selfishness by someone other than me” and it makes perfect sense.
  3. Joel Bakan, The Corporation: The Pathological Pursuit of Profit and Power (2003)
  4. Is being Chairman and CEO really the best example for a chair of a corporate governance committee to set?
  5. Stakeholder capitalism is ‘not woke’, says JPMorgan’s Jamie Dimon, Financial Times, 2 June 2022
  6. https://www.epi.org/publication/ceo-compensation-2018/